EDMUND G. BROWN, JR., GOVERNOR OF CALIFORNIA, et al., PETITIONERS v. ENTERTAINMENT MERCHANTS ASSOCIATION, et al.
Supreme Court Cases
564 U.S. 786 (2011)
Opinions
Majority Opinion Author
Antonin Scalia
Majority Participants
Concurring Participants
Dissenting Participants
(Slip Opinion) OCTOBER TERM, 2010 1 Syllabus NOTE: Where it is feasible, a syllabus (headnote) will be released, as is being done in connection with this case, at the time the opinion is issued. The syllabus constitutes no part of the opinion of the Court but has been prepared by the Reporter of Decisions for the convenience of the reader. See United States v. Detroit Timber & Lumber Co., 200 U. S. 321, 337. SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES Syllabus BROWN, GOVERNOR OF CALIFORNIA, ET AL. v. ENTERTAINMENT MERCHANTS ASSOCIATION ET AL. CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE NINTH CIRCUIT No. 08â1448. Argued November 2, 2010âDecided June 27, 2011 Respondents, representing the video-game and software industries, filed a preenforcement challenge to a California law that restricts the sale or rental of violent video games to minors. The Federal District Court concluded that the Act violated the First Amendment and permanently enjoined its enforcement. The Ninth Circuit affirmed. Held: The Act does not comport with the First Amendment. Pp. 2â18. (a) Video games qualify for First Amendment protection. Like pro tected books, plays, and movies, they communicate ideas through fa miliar literary devices and features distinctive to the medium. And âthe basic principles of freedom of speech . . . do not varyâ with a new and different communication medium. Joseph Burstyn, Inc. v. Wil son, 343 U. S. 495, 503. The most basic principleâthat government lacks the power to restrict expression because of its message, ideas, subject matter, or content, Ashcroft v. American Civil Liberties Un ion, 535 U. S. 564, 573âis subject to a few limited exceptions for his torically unprotected speech, such as obscenity, incitement, and fight ing words. But a legislature cannot create new categories of unprotected speech simply by weighing the value of a particular category against its social costs and then punishing it if it fails the test. See United States v. Stevens, 559 U. S. ___, ___. Unlike the New York law upheld in Ginsberg v. New York, 390 U. S. 629, Cali forniaâs Act does not adjust the boundaries of an existing category of unprotected speech to ensure that a definition designed for adults is not uncritically applied to children. Instead, the State wishes to cre ate a wholly new category of content-based regulation that is permis sible only for speech directed at children. That is unprecedented and 2 BROWN v. ENTERTAINMENT MERCHANTS ASSN. Syllabus mistaken. This country has no tradition of specially restricting chil drenâs access to depictions of violence. And Californiaâs claim that âinteractiveâ video games present special problems, in that the player participates in the violent action on screen and determines its out come, is unpersuasive. Pp. 2â11. (b) Because the Act imposes a restriction on the content of pro tected speech, it is invalid unless California can demonstrate that it passes strict scrutiny, i.e., it is justified by a compelling government interest and is narrowly drawn to serve that interest. R. A. V. v. St. Paul, 505 U. S. 377, 395. California cannot meet that standard. Psy chological studies purporting to show a connection between exposure to violent video games and harmful effects on children do not prove that such exposure causes minors to act aggressively. Any demon strated effects are both small and indistinguishable from effects pro duced by other media. Since California has declined to restrict those other media, e.g., Saturday morning cartoons, its video-game regula tion is wildly underinclusive, raising serious doubts about whether the State is pursuing the interest it invokes or is instead disfavoring a particular speaker or viewpoint. California also cannot show that the Actâs restrictions meet the alleged substantial need of parents who wish to restrict their childrenâs access to violent videos. The video-game industryâs voluntary rating system already accomplishes that to a large extent. Moreover, as a means of assisting parents the Act is greatly overinclusive, since not all of the children who are pro hibited from purchasing violent video games have parents who dis approve of their doing so. The Act cannot satisfy strict scrutiny. Pp. 11â18. 556 F. 3d 950, affirmed. SCALIA, J., delivered the opinion of the Court, in which KENNEDY, GINSBURG, SOTOMAYOR, and KAGAN, JJ., joined. ALITO, J., filed an opin ion concurring in the judgment, in which ROBERTS, C. J., joined. THO- MAS, J., and BREYER, J., filed dissenting opinions. Cite as: 564 U. S. ____ (2011) 1 Opinion of the Court NOTICE: This opinion is subject to formal revision before publication in the preliminary print of the United States Reports. Readers are requested to notify the Reporter of Decisions, Supreme Court of the United States, Wash ington, D. C. 20543, of any typographical or other formal errors, in order that corrections may be made before the preliminary print goes to press. SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES _________________ No. 08â1448 _________________ EDMUND G. BROWN, JR., GOVERNOR OF CAL- IFORNIA, ET AL., PETITIONERS v. ENTERTAIN- MENT MERCHANTS ASSOCIATION ET AL. ON WRIT OF CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE NINTH CIRCUIT [June 27, 2011] JUSTICE SCALIA delivered the opinion of the Court. We consider whether a California law imposing restric tions on violent video games comports with the First Amendment. I California Assembly Bill 1179 (2005), Cal. Civ. Code Ann. §§1746â1746.5 (West 2009) (Act), prohibits the sale or rental of âviolent video gamesâ to minors, and requires their packaging to be labeled â18.â The Act covers games âin which the range of options available to a player in cludes killing, maiming, dismembering, or sexually as saulting an image of a human being, if those acts are depictedâ in a manner that â[a] reasonable person, consid ering the game as a whole, would find appeals to a deviant or morbid interest of minors,â that is âpatently offensive to prevailing standards in the community as to what is suit able for minors,â and that âcauses the game, as a whole, to lack serious literary, artistic, political, or scientific value for minors.â §1746(d)(1)(A). Violation of the Act is pun ishable by a civil fine of up to $1,000. §1746.3. 2 BROWN v. ENTERTAINMENT MERCHANTS ASSN. Opinion of the Court Respondents, representing the video-game and software industries, brought a preenforcement challenge to the Act in the United States District Court for the Northern Dis trict of California. That court concluded that the Act violated the First Amendment and permanently enjoined its enforcement. Video Software Dealers Assn. v. Schwar zenegger, No. Câ05â04188 RMW (2007), App. to Pet. for Cert. 39a. The Court of Appeals affirmed, Video Software Dealers Assn. v. Schwarzenegger, 556 F. 3d 950 (CA9 2009), and we granted certiorari, 559 U. S. ____ (2010). II California correctly acknowledges that video games qualify for First Amendment protection. The Free Speech Clause exists principally to protect discourse on public matters, but we have long recognized that it is difficult to distinguish politics from entertainment, and dangerous to try. âEveryone is familiar with instances of propaganda through fiction. What is one manâs amusement, teaches anotherâs doctrine.â Winters v. New York, 333 U. S. 507, 510 (1948). Like the protected books, plays, and movies that preceded them, video games communicate ideasâand even social messagesâthrough many familiar literary devices (such as characters, dialogue, plot, and music) and through features distinctive to the medium (such as the playerâs interaction with the virtual world). That suffices to confer First Amendment protection. Under our Consti tution, âesthetic and moral judgments about art and lit erature . . . are for the individual to make, not for the Government to decree, even with the mandate or approval of a majority.â United States v. Playboy Entertainment Group, Inc., 529 U. S. 803, 818 (2000). And whatever the challenges of applying the Constitution to ever-advancing technology, âthe basic principles of freedom of speech and the press, like the First Amendmentâs command, do not varyâ when a new and different medium for communica Cite as: 564 U. S. ____ (2011) 3 Opinion of the Court tion appears. Joseph Burstyn, Inc. v. Wilson, 343 U. S. 495, 503 (1952). The most basic of those principles is this: â[A]s a general matter, . . . government has no power to restrict expres sion because of its message, its ideas, its subject matter, or its content.â Ashcroft v. American Civil Liberties Union, 535 U. S. 564, 573 (2002) (internal quotation marks omit ted). There are of course exceptions. â âFrom 1791 to the present,â . . . the First Amendment has âpermitted restric tions upon the content of speech in a few limited areas,â and has never âinclude[d] a freedom to disregard these traditional limitations.â â United States v. Stevens, 559 U. S. ___, ___ (2010) (slip op., at 5) (quoting R. A. V. v. St. Paul, 505 U. S. 377, 382â383 (1992)). These limited ar easâsuch as obscenity, Roth v. United States, 354 U. S. 476, 483 (1957), incitement, Brandenburg v. Ohio, 395 U. S. 444, 447â449 (1969) (per curiam), and fighting words, Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, 315 U. S. 568, 572 (1942)ârepresent âwell-defined and narrowly limited classes of speech, the prevention and punishment of which have never been thought to raise any Constitutional prob lem,â id., at 571â572. Last Term, in Stevens, we held that new categories of unprotected speech may not be added to the list by a legislature that concludes certain speech is too harmful to be tolerated. Stevens concerned a federal statute purport ing to criminalize the creation, sale, or possession of cer tain depictions of animal cruelty. See 18 U. S. C. §48 (amended 2010). The statute covered depictions âin which a living animal is intentionally maimed, mutilated, tor tured, wounded, or killedâ if that harm to the animal was illegal where the âthe creation, sale, or possession t[ook] place,â §48(c)(1). A saving clause largely borrowed from our obscenity jurisprudence, see Miller v. California, 413 U. S. 15, 24 (1973), exempted depictions with âserious religious, political, scientific, educational, journalistic, 4 BROWN v. ENTERTAINMENT MERCHANTS ASSN. Opinion of the Court historical, or artistic value,â §48(b). We held that statute to be an impermissible content-based restriction on speech. There was no American tradition of forbidding the depiction of animal crueltyâthough States have long had laws against committing it. The Government argued in Stevens that lack of a his torical warrant did not matter; that it could create new categories of unprotected speech by applying a âsimple balancing testâ that weighs the value of a particular cate gory of speech against its social costs and then punishes that category of speech if it fails the test. Stevens, 559 U. S., at ___ (slip op., at 7). We emphatically rejected that âstartling and dangerousâ proposition. Ibid. âMaybe there are some categories of speech that have been historically unprotected, but have not yet been specifically identified or discussed as such in our case law.â Id., at ___ (slip op., at 9). But without persuasive evidence that a novel re striction on content is part of a long (if heretofore unrec ognized) tradition of proscription, a legislature may not revise the âjudgment [of] the American people,â embodied in the First Amendment, âthat the benefits of its restric tions on the Government outweigh the costs.â Id., at ___ (slip op., at 7). That holding controls this case.1 As in Stevens, Califor ââââââ 1 JUSTICE ALITO distinguishes Stevens on several grounds that seem to us ill founded. He suggests, post, at 10 (opinion concurring in judg ment), that Stevens did not apply strict scrutiny. If that is so (and we doubt it), it would make this an a fortiori case. He says, post, at 9, 10, that the California Act punishes the sale or rental rather than the âcreationâ or âpossessionâ of violent depictions. That distinction ap pears nowhere in Stevens itself, and for good reason: It would make permissible the prohibition of printing or selling booksâthough not the writing of them. Whether government regulation applies to creating, distributing, or consuming speech makes no difference. And finally, JUSTICE ALITO points out, post, at 10, that Stevens âleft open the possi bility that a more narrowly drawn statuteâ would be constitutional. True, but entirely irrelevant. Stevens said, 559 U. S., at ___ (slip op., at Cite as: 564 U. S. ____ (2011) 5 Opinion of the Court nia has tried to make violent-speech regulation look like obscenity regulation by appending a saving clause re quired for the latter. That does not suffice. Our cases have been clear that the obscenity exception to the First Amendment does not cover whatever a legislature finds shocking, but only depictions of âsexual conduct,â Miller, supra, at 24. See also Cohen v. California, 403 U. S. 15, 20 (1971); Roth, supra, at 487, and n. 20. Stevens was not the first time we have encountered and rejected a Stateâs attempt to shoehorn speech about vio lence into obscenity. In Winters, we considered a New York criminal statute âforbid[ding] the massing of stories of bloodshed and lust in such a way as to incite to crime against the person,â 333 U. S., at 514. The New York Court of Appeals upheld the provision as a law against obscenity. â[T]here can be no more precise test of written indecency or obscenity,â it said, âthan the continuing and changeable experience of the community as to what types of books are likely to bring about the corruption of public morals or other analogous injury to the public order. â Id., at 514 (internal quotation marks omitted). That is of course the same expansive view of governmental power to abridge the freedom of speech based on interest-balancing that we rejected in Stevens. Our opinion in Winters, which concluded that the New York statute failed a heightened vagueness standard applicable to restrictions upon speech entitled to First Amendment protection, 333 U. S., at 517â 519, made clear that violence is not part of the obscenity that the Constitution permits to be regulated. The speech reached by the statute contained âno indecency or obscen ity in any sense heretofore known to the law.â Id., at 519. ââââââ 19), that the âcrush-videoâ statute at issue there might pass muster if it were limited to videos of acts of animal cruelty that violated the law where the acts were performed. There is no contention that any of the virtual characters depicted in the imaginative videos at issue here are criminally liable. 6 BROWN v. ENTERTAINMENT MERCHANTS ASSN. Opinion of the Court Because speech about violence is not obscene, it is of no consequence that Californiaâs statute mimics the New York statute regulating obscenity-for-minors that we upheld in Ginsberg v. New York, 390 U. S. 629 (1968). That case approved a prohibition on the sale to minors of sexual material that would be obscene from the perspec tive of a child.2 We held that the legislature could âadjus[t] the definition of obscenity âto social realities by permitting the appeal of this type of material to be as sessed in terms of the sexual interests . . .â of . . . minors. â Id., at 638 (quoting Mishkin v. New York, 383 U. S. 502, 509 (1966)). And because âobscenity is not protected expression,â the New York statute could be sustained so long as the legislatureâs judgment that the proscribed materials were harmful to children âwas not irrational.â 390 U. S., at 641. The California Act is something else entirely. It does not adjust the boundaries of an existing category of unpro tected speech to ensure that a definition designed for adults is not uncritically applied to children. California does not argue that it is empowered to prohibit selling offensively violent works to adultsâand it is wise not to, since that is but a hairâs breadth from the argument re jected in Stevens. Instead, it wishes to create a wholly new category of content-based regulation that is permissi ble only for speech directed at children. That is unprecedented and mistaken. â[M]inors are ââââââ 2 The statute in Ginsberg restricted the sale of certain depictions of ânudity, sexual conduct, sexual excitement, or sado-masochistic abuse,â that were ââ[h]armful to minors.â â A depiction was harmful to minors if it: â(i) predominantly appeals to the prurient, shameful or morbid interests of minors, and â(ii) is patently offensive to prevailing standards in the adult commu nity as a whole with respect to what is suitable material for minors, and â(iii) is utterly without redeeming social importance for minors.â 390 U. S., at 646 (Appendix A to opinion of the Court) (quoting N. Y. Penal Law §484âh(1)(f)). Cite as: 564 U. S. ____ (2011) 7 Opinion of the Court entitled to a significant measure of First Amendment protection, and only in relatively narrow and well-defined circumstances may government bar public dissemination of protected materials to them.â Erznoznik v. Jackson ville, 422 U. S. 205, 212â213 (1975) (citation omitted). No doubt a State possesses legitimate power to protect chil dren from harm, Ginsberg, supra, at 640â641; Prince v. Massachusetts, 321 U. S. 158, 165 (1944), but that does not include a free-floating power to restrict the ideas to which children may be exposed. âSpeech that is neither obscene as to youths nor subject to some other legitimate proscription cannot be suppressed solely to protect the young from ideas or images that a legislative body thinks unsuitable for them.â Erznoznik, supra, at 213â214.3 ââââââ 3 JUSTICE THOMAS ignores the holding of Erznoznik, and denies that persons under 18 have any constitutional right to speak or be spoken to without their parentsâ consent. He cites no case, state or federal, supporting this view, and to our knowledge there is none. Most of his dissent is devoted to the proposition that parents have traditionally had the power to control what their children hear and say. This is true enough. And it perhaps follows from this that the state has the power to enforce parental prohibitionsâto require, for example, that the promoters of a rock concert exclude those minors whose parents have advised the promoters that their children are forbidden to attend. But it does not follow that the state has the power to prevent children from hearing or saying anything without their parentsâ prior consent. The latter would mean, for example, that it could be made criminal to admit persons under 18 to a political rally without their parentsâ prior written consentâeven a political rally in support of laws against corporal punishment of children, or laws in favor of greater rights for minors. And what is good for First Amendment rights of speech must be good for First Amendment rights of religion as well: It could be made crimi nal to admit a person under 18 to church, or to give a person under 18 a religious tract, without his parentsâ prior consent. Our point is not, as JUSTICE THOMAS believes, post, at 16, n. 2, merely that such laws are âundesirable.â They are obviously an infringement upon the religious freedom of young people and those who wish to proselytize young people. Such laws do not enforce parental authority over childrenâs speech and religion; they impose governmental authority, subject only 8 BROWN v. ENTERTAINMENT MERCHANTS ASSN. Opinion of the Court Californiaâs argument would fare better if there were a longstanding tradition in this country of specially restrict ing childrenâs access to depictions of violence, but there is none. Certainly the books we give children to readâor read to them when they are youngerâcontain no shortage of gore. Grimmâs Fairy Tales, for example, are grim in deed. As her just deserts for trying to poison Snow White, the wicked queen is made to dance in red hot slippers âtill she fell dead on the floor, a sad example of envy and jeal ousy.â The Complete Brothers Grimm Fairy Tales 198 (2006 ed.). Cinderellaâs evil stepsisters have their eyes pecked out by doves. Id., at 95. And Hansel and Gretel (children!) kill their captor by baking her in an oven. Id., at 54. High-school reading lists are full of similar fare. Homerâs Odysseus blinds Polyphemus the Cyclops by grinding out his eye with a heated stake. The Odyssey of Homer, Book IX, p. 125 (S. Butcher & A. Lang transls. 1909) (âEven so did we seize the fiery-pointed brand and whirled it round in his eye, and the blood flowed about the heated bar. And the breath of the flame singed his eyelids and brows all about, as the ball of the eye burnt away, and the roots thereof crackled in the flameâ). In the Inferno, Dante and Virgil watch corrupt politicians struggle to stay submerged beneath a lake of boiling pitch, lest they be skewered by devils above the surface. Canto XXI, pp. 187â189 (A. Mandelbaum transl. Bantam Classic ed. 1982). And Goldingâs Lord of the Flies recounts how a schoolboy called Piggy is savagely murdered by other ââââââ to a parental veto. In the absence of any precedent for state control, uninvited by the parents, over a childâs speech and religion (JUSTICE THOMAS cites none), and in the absence of any justification for such control that would satisfy strict scrutiny, those laws must be unconsti tutional. This argument is not, as JUSTICE THOMAS asserts, âcircular,â ibid. It is the absence of any historical warrant or compelling justifica tion for such restrictions, not our ipse dixit, that renders them invalid. Cite as: 564 U. S. ____ (2011) 9 Opinion of the Court children while marooned on an island. W. Golding, Lord of the Flies 208â209 (1997 ed.).4 This is not to say that minorsâ consumption of violent entertainment has never encountered resistance. In the 1800âs, dime novels depicting crime and âpenny dreadfulsâ (named for their price and content) were blamed in some quarters for juvenile delinquency. See Brief for Cato Institute as Amicus Curiae 6â7. When motion pictures came along, they became the villains instead. âThe days when the police looked upon dime novels as the most dangerous of textbooks in the school for crime are drawing to a close. . . . They say that the moving picture machine . . . tends even more than did the dime novel to turn the thoughts of the easily influenced to paths which some times lead to prison.â Moving Pictures as Helps to Crime, N. Y. Times, Feb. 21, 1909, quoted in Brief for Cato Insti tute, at 8. For a time, our Court did permit broad censor ship of movies because of their capacity to be âused for evil,â see Mutual Film Corp. v. Industrial Commân of Ohio, 236 U. S. 230, 242 (1915), but we eventually reversed course, Joseph Burstyn, Inc., 343 U. S., at 502; see also Erznoznik, supra, at 212â214 (invalidating a drive-in ââââââ 4 JUSTICE ALITO accuses us of pronouncing that playing violent video games âis not different in âkindâ â from reading violent literature. Post, at 2. Well of course it is different in kind, but not in a way that causes the provision and viewing of violent video games, unlike the provision and reading of books, not to be expressive activity and hence not to enjoy First Amendment protection. Reading Dante is unquestionably more cultured and intellectually edifying than playing Mortal Kombat. But these cultural and intellectual differences are not constitutional ones. Crudely violent video games, tawdry TV shows, and cheap novels and magazines are no less forms of speech than The Divine Comedy, and restrictions upon them must survive strict scrutinyâa question to which we devote our attention in Part III, infra. Even if we can see in them ânothing of any possible value to society . . . , they are as much entitled to the protection of free speech as the best of literature.â Winters v. New York, 333 U. S. 507, 510 (1948). 10 BROWN v. ENTERTAINMENT MERCHANTS ASSN. Opinion of the Court movies restriction designed to protect children). Radio dramas were next, and then came comic books. Brief for Cato Institute, at 10â11. Many in the late 1940âs and early 1950âs blamed comic books for fostering a âpreoccu pation with violence and horrorâ among the young, leading to a rising juvenile crime rate. See Note, Regulation of Comic Books, 68 Harv. L. Rev. 489, 490 (1955). But efforts to convince Congress to restrict comic books failed. Brief for Comic Book Legal Defense Fund as Amicus Curiae 11â 15.5 And, of course, after comic books came television and music lyrics. California claims that video games present special problems because they are âinteractive,â in that the player participates in the violent action on screen and determines its outcome. The latter feature is nothing new: Since at least the publication of The Adventures of You: Sugar cane Island in 1969, young readers of choose-your-own adventure stories have been able to make decisions that determine the plot by following instructions about which page to turn to. Cf. Interactive Digital Software Assn. v. St. Louis County, 329 F. 3d 954, 957â958 (CA8 2003). As for the argument that video games enable participation in the violent action, that seems to us more a matter of de gree than of kind. As Judge Posner has observed, all ââââââ 5 The crusade against comic books was led by a psychiatrist, Frederic Wertham, who told the Senate Judiciary Committee that âas long as the crime comic books industry exists in its present forms there are no secure homes.â Juvenile Delinquency (Comic Books): Hearings before the Subcommittee to Investigate Juvenile Delinquency, 83d Cong., 2d Sess., 84 (1954). Werthamâs objections extended even to Superman comics, which he described as âparticularly injurious to the ethical development of children.â Id., at 86. Werthamâs crusade did convince the New York Legislature to pass a ban on the sale of certain comic books to minors, but it was vetoed by Governor Thomas Dewey on the ground that it was unconstitutional given our opinion in Winters, supra. See People v. Bookcase, Inc., 14 N. Y. 2d 409, 412â413, 201 N. E. 2d 14, 15â16 (1964). Cite as: 564 U. S. ____ (2011) 11 Opinion of the Court literature is interactive. â[T]he better it is, the more interactive. Literature when it is successful draws the reader into the story, makes him identify with the charac ters, invites him to judge them and quarrel with them, to experience their joys and sufferings as the readerâs own.â American Amusement Machine Assn. v. Kendrick, 244 F. 3d 572, 577 (CA7 2001) (striking down a similar restric tion on violent video games). JUSTICE ALITO has done considerable independent re search to identify, see post, at 14â15, nn. 13â18, video games in which âthe violence is astounding,â post, at 14. âVictims are dismembered, decapitated, disemboweled, set on fire, and chopped into little pieces. . . . Blood gushes, splatters, and pools.â Ibid. JUSTICE ALITO recounts all these disgusting video games in order to disgust usâbut disgust is not a valid basis for restricting expression. And the same is true of JUSTICE ALITOâs description, post, at 14â15, of those video games he has discovered that have a racial or ethnic motive for their violenceââ âethnic clean singâ [of] . . . African Americans, Latinos, or Jews.â To what end does he relate this? Does it somehow increase the âaggressivenessâ that California wishes to suppress? Who knows? But it does arouse the readerâs ire, and the readerâs desire to put an end to this horrible message. Thus, ironically, JUSTICE ALITOâs argument highlights the precise danger posed by the California Act: that the ideas expressed by speechâwhether it be violence, or gore, or racismâand not its objective effects, may be the real reason for governmental proscription. III Because the Act imposes a restriction on the content of protected speech, it is invalid unless California can dem onstrate that it passes strict scrutinyâthat is, unless it is justified by a compelling government interest and is nar rowly drawn to serve that interest. R. A. V., 505 U. S., at 12 BROWN v. ENTERTAINMENT MERCHANTS ASSN. Opinion of the Court 395. The State must specifically identify an âactual prob lemâ in need of solving, Playboy, 529 U. S., at 822â823, and the curtailment of free speech must be actually neces sary to the solution, see R. A. V., supra, at 395. That is a demanding standard. âIt is rare that a regulation restrict ing speech because of its content will ever be permissible.â Playboy, supra, at 818. California cannot meet that standard. At the outset, it acknowledges that it cannot show a direct causal link between violent video games and harm to minors. Rather, relying upon our decision in Turner Broadcasting System, Inc. v. FCC, 512 U. S. 622 (1994), the State claims that it need not produce such proof because the legislature can make a predictive judgment that such a link exists, based on competing psychological studies. But reliance on Turner Broadcasting is misplaced. That decision applied intermediate scrutiny to a content-neutral regulation. Id., at 661â662. Californiaâs burden is much higher, and because it bears the risk of uncertainty, see Playboy, supra, at 816â817, ambiguous proof will not suffice. The Stateâs evidence is not compelling. California relies primarily on the research of Dr. Craig Anderson and a few other research psychologists whose studies purport to show a connection between exposure to violent video games and harmful effects on children. These studies have been rejected by every court to consider them,6 and with good reason: They do not prove that violent video ââââââ 6 See Video Software Dealers Assn. v. Schwarzenegger, 556 F. 3d 950, 963â964 (CA9 2009); Interactive Digital Software Assn. v. St. Louis County, 329 F. 3d 954 (CA8 2003); American Amusement Machine Assn. v. Kendrick, 244 F. 3d 572, 578â579 (CA7 2001); Entertainment Soft ware Assn. v. Foti,
, 832â833 (MD La. 2006); Enter tainment Software Assn. v. Hatch,
443 F. Supp. 2d 1065
, 1070 (Minn. 2006), aff âd, 519 F. 3d 768 (CA8 2008); Entertainment Software Assn. v. Granholm,
, 653 (ED Mich. 2006); Entertainment Software Assn. v. Blagojevich,
, 1063 (ND Ill. 2005), aff âd, 469 F. 3d 641 (CA7 2006). Cite as: 564 U. S. ____ (2011) 13 Opinion of the Court games cause minors to act aggressively (which would at least be a beginning). Instead, â[n]early all of the research is based on correlation, not evidence of causation, and most of the studies suffer from significant, admitted flaws in methodology.â Video Software Dealers Assn. 556 F. 3d, at 964. They show at best some correlation between expo sure to violent entertainment and minuscule real-world effects, such as childrenâs feeling more aggressive or mak ing louder noises in the few minutes after playing a vio lent game than after playing a nonviolent game.7 Even taking for granted Dr. Andersonâs conclusions that violent video games produce some effect on childrenâs feelings of aggression, those effects are both small and indistinguishable from effects produced by other media. In his testimony in a similar lawsuit, Dr. Anderson admit ted that the âeffect sizesâ of childrenâs exposure to violent video games are âabout the sameâ as that produced by their exposure to violence on television. App. 1263. And he admits that the same effects have been found when children watch cartoons starring Bugs Bunny or the Road Runner, id., at 1304, or when they play video games like Sonic the Hedgehog that are rated âEâ (appropriate for all ages), id., at 1270, or even when they âvie[w] a picture of a gun,â id., at 1315â1316.8 ââââââ 7 One study, for example, found that children who had just finished playing violent video games were more likely to fill in the blank letter in âexplo_eâ with a âdâ (so that it reads âexplodeâ) than with an ârâ (âexploreâ). App. 496, 506 (internal quotation marks omitted). The prevention of this phenomenon, which might have been anticipated with common sense, is not a compelling state interest. 8JUSTICE ALITO is mistaken in thinking that we fail to take account of ânew and rapidly evolving technology,â post, at 1. The studies in question pertain to that new and rapidly evolving technology, and fail to show, with the degree of certitude that strict scrutiny requires, that this subject-matter restriction on speech is justified. Nor is JUSTICE ALITO correct in attributing to us the view that âviolent video games really present no serious problem.â Post, at 2. Perhaps they do present 14 BROWN v. ENTERTAINMENT MERCHANTS ASSN. Opinion of the Court Of course, California has (wisely) declined to restrict Saturday morning cartoons, the sale of games rated for young children, or the distribution of pictures of guns. The consequence is that its regulation is wildly underin clusive when judged against its asserted justification, which in our view is alone enough to defeat it. Underin clusiveness raises serious doubts about whether the gov ernment is in fact pursuing the interest it invokes, rather than disfavoring a particular speaker or viewpoint. See City of Ladue v. Gilleo, 512 U. S. 43, 51 (1994); Florida Star v. B. J. F., 491 U. S. 524, 540 (1989). Here, Califor nia has singled out the purveyors of video games for disfa vored treatmentâat least when compared to booksellers, cartoonists, and movie producersâand has given no per suasive reason why. The Act is also seriously underinclusive in another respectâand a respect that renders irrelevant the conten tions of the concurrence and the dissents that video games ââââââ a problem, and perhaps none of us would allow our own children to play them. But there are all sorts of âproblemsââsome of them surely more serious than this oneâthat cannot be addressed by governmental restriction of free expression: for example, the problem of encouraging anti-Semitism (National Socialist Party of America v. Skokie, 432 U. S. 43 (1977) (per curiam)), the problem of spreading a political philosophy hostile to the Constitution (Noto v. United States, 367 U. S. 290 (1961)), or the problem of encouraging disrespect for the Nationâs flag (Texas v. Johnson, 491 U. S. 397 (1989)). JUSTICE BREYER would hold that California has satisfied strict scrutiny based upon his own research into the issue of the harmfulness of violent video games. See post, at 20â35 (Appendixes to dissenting opinion) (listing competing academic articles discussing the harmful ness vel non of violent video games). The vast preponderance of this research is outside the recordâand in any event we do not see how it could lead to JUSTICE BREYERâs conclusion, since he admits he cannot say whether the studies on his side are right or wrong. Post, at 15. Similarly, JUSTICE ALITO says he is not âsureâ whether there are any constitutionally dispositive differences between video games and other media. Post, at 2. If that is so, then strict scrutiny plainly has not been satisfied. Cite as: 564 U. S. ____ (2011) 15 Opinion of the Court are qualitatively different from other portrayals of vio lence. The California Legislature is perfectly willing to leave this dangerous, mind-altering material in the hands of children so long as one parent (or even an aunt or uncle) says itâs OK. And there are not even any requirements as to how this parental or avuncular relationship is to be verified; apparently the childâs or putative parentâs, auntâs, or uncleâs say-so suffices. That is not how one addresses a serious social problem. California claims that the Act is justified in aid of pa rental authority: By requiring that the purchase of violent video games can be made only by adults, the Act ensures that parents can decide what games are appropriate. At the outset, we note our doubts that punishing third parties for conveying protected speech to children just in case their parents disapprove of that speech is a proper gov ernmental means of aiding parental authority. Accepting that position would largely vitiate the rule that âonly in relatively narrow and well-defined circumstances may government bar public dissemination of protected materi als to [minors].â Erznoznik, 422 U. S., at 212â213. But leaving that aside, California cannot show that the Actâs restrictions meet a substantial need of parents who wish to restrict their childrenâs access to violent video games but cannot do so. The video-game industry has in place a voluntary rating system designed to inform con sumers about the content of games. The system, imple mented by the Entertainment Software Rating Board (ESRB), assigns age-specific ratings to each video game submitted: EC (Early Childhood); E (Everyone); E10+ (Everyone 10 and older); T (Teens); M (17 and older); and AO (Adults Onlyâ18 and older). App. 86. The Video Software Dealers Association encourages retailers to prominently display information about the ESRB system in their stores; to refrain from renting or selling adults only games to minors; and to rent or sell âMâ rated games 16 BROWN v. ENTERTAINMENT MERCHANTS ASSN. Opinion of the Court to minors only with parental consent. Id., at 47. In 2009, the Federal Trade Commission (FTC) found that, as a result of this system, âthe video game industry outpaces the movie and music industriesâ in â(1) restricting target marketing of mature-rated products to children; (2) clearly and prominently disclosing rating information; and (3) re stricting childrenâs access to mature-rated products at retail.â FTC, Report to Congress, Marketing Violent Entertainment to Children 30 (Dec. 2009), online at http:// www.ftc.gov/os/2009/12/P994511violententertainment.pdf (as visited June 24, 2011, and available in Clerk of Courtâs case file) (FTC Report). This system does much to ensure that minors cannot purchase seriously violent games on their own, and that parents who care about the matter can readily evaluate the games their children bring home. Filling the remaining modest gap in concerned-parentsâ control can hardly be a compelling state interest.9 And finally, the Actâs purported aid to parental author ity is vastly overinclusive. Not all of the children who are forbidden to purchase violent video games on their own have parents who care whether they purchase violent video games. While some of the legislationâs effect may indeed be in support of what some parents of the re stricted children actually want, its entire effect is only in support of what the State thinks parents ought to want. This is not the narrow tailoring to âassisting parentsâ that ââââââ 9 JUSTICE BREYER concludes that the remaining gap is compelling because, according to the FTCâs report, some â20% of those under 17 are still able to buy M-rated games.â Post, at 18 (citing FTC Report 28). But some gap in compliance is unavoidable. The sale of alcohol to minors, for example, has long been illegal, but a 2005 study suggests that about 18% of retailers still sell alcohol to those under the drinking age. Brief for State of Rhode Island et al. as Amici Curiae 18. Even if the sale of violent video games to minors could be deterred further by increasing regulation, the government does not have a compelling interest in each marginal percentage point by which its goals are advanced. Cite as: 564 U. S. ____ (2011) 17 Opinion of the Court restriction of First Amendment rights requires. * * * Californiaâs effort to regulate violent video games is the latest episode in a long series of failed attempts to censor violent entertainment for minors. While we have pointed out above that some of the evidence brought forward to support the harmfulness of video games is unpersuasive, we do not mean to demean or disparage the concerns that underlie the attempt to regulate themâconcerns that may and doubtless do prompt a good deal of parental oversight. We have no business passing judgment on the view of the California Legislature that violent video games (or, for that matter, any other forms of speech) corrupt the young or harm their moral development. Our task is only to say whether or not such works constitute a âwell-defined and narrowly limited clas[s] of speech, the prevention and punishment of which have never been thought to raise any Constitutional problem,â Chaplinsky, 315 U. S., at 571â 572 (the answer plainly is no); and if not, whether the regulation of such works is justified by that high degree of necessity we have described as a compelling state interest (it is not). Even where the protection of children is the object, the constitutional limits on governmental action apply. Californiaâs legislation straddles the fence between (1) addressing a serious social problem and (2) helping con cerned parents control their children. Both ends are legitimate, but when they affect First Amendment rights they must be pursued by means that are neither seriously underinclusive nor seriously overinclusive. See Church of Lukumi Babalu Aye, Inc. v. Hialeah, 508 U. S. 520, 546 (1993). As a means of protecting children from portrayals of violence, the legislation is seriously underinclusive, not only because it excludes portrayals other than video games, but also because it permits a parental or avuncular 18 BROWN v. ENTERTAINMENT MERCHANTS ASSN. Opinion of the Court veto. And as a means of assisting concerned parents it is seriously overinclusive because it abridges the First Amendment rights of young people whose parents (and aunts and uncles) think violent video games are a harm less pastime. And the overbreadth in achieving one goal is not cured by the underbreadth in achieving the other. Legislation such as this, which is neither fish nor fowl, cannot survive strict scrutiny. We affirm the judgment below. It is so ordered. Cite as: 564 U. S. ____ (2011) 1 ALITO, J., concurring in judgment SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES _________________ No. 08â1448 _________________ EDMUND G. BROWN, JR., GOVERNOR OF CAL- IFORNIA, ET AL., PETITIONERS v. ENTERTAIN- MENT MERCHANTS ASSOCIATION ET AL. ON WRIT OF CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE NINTH CIRCUIT [June 27, 2011] JUSTICE ALITO, with whom THE CHIEF JUSTICE joins, concurring in the judgment. The California statute that is before us in this case represents a pioneering effort to address what the state legislature and others regard as a potentially serious social problem: the effect of exceptionally violent video games on impressionable minors, who often spend count less hours immersed in the alternative worlds that these games create. Although the California statute is well intentioned, its terms are not framed with the precision that the Constitution demands, and I therefore agree with the Court that this particular law cannot be sustained. I disagree, however, with the approach taken in the Courtâs opinion. In considering the application of un changing constitutional principles to new and rapidly evolving technology, this Court should proceed with cau tion. We should make every effort to understand the new technology. We should take into account the possibility that developing technology may have important societal implications that will become apparent only with time. We should not jump to the conclusion that new technology is fundamentally the same as some older thing with which we are familiar. And we should not hastily dismiss the judgment of legislators, who may be in a better position 2 BROWN v. ENTERTAINMENT MERCHANTS ASSN. ALITO, J., concurring in judgment than we are to assess the implications of new technology. The opinion of the Court exhibits none of this caution. In the view of the Court, all those concerned about the effects of violent video gamesâfederal and state legisla tors, educators, social scientists, and parentsâare unduly fearful, for violent video games really present no serious problem. See ante, at 10â13, 15â16. Spending hour upon hour controlling the actions of a character who guns down scores of innocent victims is not different in âkindâ from reading a description of violence in a work of literature. See ante, at 10â11. The Court is sure of this; I am not. There are reasons to suspect that the experience of playing violent video games just might be very different from reading a book, listening to the radio, or watching a movie or a television show. I Respondents in this case, representing the video-game industry, ask us to strike down the California law on two grounds: The broad ground adopted by the Court and the narrower ground that the lawâs definition of âviolent video game,â see Cal. Civ. Code Ann. §1746(d)(1)(A) (West 2009), is impermissibly vague. See Brief for Respondents 23â61. Because I agree with the latter argument, I see no need to reach the broader First Amendment issues addressed by the Court.1 A Due process requires that laws give people of ordinary intelligence fair notice of what is prohibited. Grayned v. City of Rockford, 408 U. S. 104, 108 (1972). The lack of such notice in a law that regulates expression âraises ââââââ 1 It is well established that a judgment may be affirmed on an alter native ground that was properly raised but not addressed by the lower court. Washington v. Confederated Bands and Tribes of Yakima Nation, 439 U. S. 463, 478, n. 20 (1979). Cite as: 564 U. S. ____ (2011) 3 ALITO, J., concurring in judgment special First Amendment concerns because of its obvious chilling effect on free speech.â Reno v. American Civil Liberties Union, 521 U. S. 844, 871â872 (1997). Vague laws force potential speakers to â âsteer far wider of the unlawful zoneâ . . . than if the boundaries of the forbidden areas were clearly marked.â Baggett v. Bullitt, 377 U. S. 360, 372 (1964) (quoting Speiser v. Randall, 357 U. S. 513, 526 (1958)). While âperfect clarity and precise guidance have never been required even of regulations that restrict expressive activity,â Ward v. Rock Against Racism, 491 U. S. 781, 794 (1989), âgovernment may regulate in the areaâ of First Amendment freedoms âonly with narrow specificity,â NAACP v. Button, 371 U. S. 415, 433 (1963); see also Hoffman Estates v. Flipside, Hoffman Estates, Inc., 455 U. S. 489, 499 (1982). These principles apply to laws that regulate expression for the purpose of protecting children. See Interstate Circuit, Inc. v. Dallas, 390 U. S. 676, 689 (1968). Here, the California law does not define âviolent video gamesâ with the ânarrow specificityâ that the Constitution demands. In an effort to avoid First Amendment prob lems, the California Legislature modeled its violent video game statute on the New York law that this Court upheld in Ginsberg v. New York, 390 U. S. 629 (1968)âa law that prohibited the sale of certain sexually related materials to minors, see id., at 631â633. But the California Legisla ture departed from the Ginsberg model in an important respect, and the legislature overlooked important differ ences between the materials falling within the scope of the two statutes. B The law at issue in Ginsberg prohibited the sale to minors of materials that were deemed âharmful to mi nors,â and the law defined âharmful to minorsâ simply by adding the words âfor minorsâ to each element of the 4 BROWN v. ENTERTAINMENT MERCHANTS ASSN. ALITO, J., concurring in judgment definition of obscenity set out in what were then the Courtâs leading obscenity decisions, see Roth v. United States, 354 U. S. 476 (1957), and Book Named âJohn Cle landâs Memoirs of a Woman of Pleasureâ v. Attorney Gen eral of Mass., 383 U. S. 413 (1966). Seeking to bring its violent video game law within the protection of Ginsberg, the California Legislature began with the obscenity test adopted in Miller v. California, 413 U. S. 15 (1973), a decision that revised the obscenity tests previously set out in Roth and Memoirs. The legislature then made certain modifications to accommodate the aim of the violent video game law. Under Miller, an obscenity statute must contain a thresh old limitation that restricts the statuteâs scope to specifi cally described âhard coreâ materials. See 413 U. S., at 23â25, 27. Materials that fall within this âhard coreâ category may be deemed to be obscene if three additional requirements are met: (1) an âaverage person, applying contemporary com munity standards [must] find . . . the work, taken as a whole, appeals to the prurient interestâ; (2) âthe work [must] depic[t] or describ[e], in a pat ently offensive way, sexual conduct specifically de fined by the applicable state law; andâ (3) âthe work, taken as a whole, [must] lac[k] serious literary, artistic, political, or scientific value.â Id., at 24 (internal quotation marks omitted). Adapting these standards, the California law imposes the following threshold limitation: â[T]he range of options available to a player [must] includ[e] killing, maiming, dismembering, or sexually assaulting an image of a hu man being.â §1746(d)(1). Any video game that meets this threshold test is subject to the lawâs restrictions if it also satisfies three further requirements: â(i) A reasonable person, considering the game as a Cite as: 564 U. S. ____ (2011) 5 ALITO, J., concurring in judgment whole, would find [the game] appeals to a deviant or morbid interest of minors. â(ii) It is patently offensive to prevailing standards in the community as to what is suitable for minors. â(iii) It causes the game, as a whole, to lack serious literary, artistic, political, or scientific value for mi nors.â §1746(d)(1)(A).2 C The first important difference between the Ginsberg law and the California violent video game statute concerns their respective threshold requirements. As noted, the Ginsberg law built upon the test for adult obscenity, and the current adult obscenity test, which was set out in Miller, requires an obscenity statute to contain a threshold limitation that restricts the statuteâs coverage to specifi cally defined âhard coreâ depictions. See 413 U. S., at 23â 25, 27. The Miller Court gave as an example a statute that applies to only â[p]atently offensive representations or descriptions of ultimate sexual acts,â âmasturbation, excretory functions, and lewd exhibition of the genitals.â Id., at 25. The Miller Court clearly viewed this threshold limitation as serving a vital notice function. âWe are satisfied,â the Court wrote, âthat these specific prerequi sites will provide fair notice to a dealer in such materials that his public and commercial activities may bring prose cution.â Id., at 27; see also Reno, supra, at 873 (observing that Millerâs threshold limitation âreduces the vagueness ââââââ 2 Under the California law, a game that meets the threshold require ment set out in text also qualifies as âviolentâ if it â[e]nables the player to virtually inflict serious injury upon images of human beings or characters with substantially human characteristics in a manner which is especially heinous, cruel, or depraved in that it involves torture or serious physical abuse to the victim.â §1746(d)(1)(B). In the Court of Appeals, California conceded that this alternative definition is uncon stitutional, 556 F. 3d 950, 954, n. 5 (CA9 2009), and therefore only the requirements set out in text are now before us. 6 BROWN v. ENTERTAINMENT MERCHANTS ASSN. ALITO, J., concurring in judgment inherent in the open-ended term âpatently offensiveâ â).3 By contrast, the threshold requirement of the California law does not perform the narrowing function served by the limitation in Miller. At least when Miller was decided, depictions of âhard coreâ sexual conduct were not a com mon feature of mainstream entertainment. But nothing similar can be said about much of the conduct covered by the California law. It provides that a video game cannot qualify as âviolentâ unless âthe range of options available to a player includes killing, maiming, dismembering, or sexually assaulting an image of a human being.â §1746(d)(1). For better or worse, our society has long regarded many depictions of killing and maiming4 as suitable features of popular entertainment, including entertainment that is widely available to minors. The California lawâs threshold requirement would more closely resemble the limitation in Miller if it targeted a narrower class of graphic depictions. Because of this feature of the California lawâs threshold test, the work of providing fair notice is left in large part to the three requirements that follow, but those elements are also not up to the task. In drafting the violent video game law, the California Legislature could have made its own judgment regarding the kind and degree of violence that is acceptable in games played by minors (or by minors in particular age groups). Instead, the legislature relied on undefined societal or community standards. ââââââ 3 The provision of New York law under which the petitioner was con victed in Ginsberg was framed with similar specificity. This provision applied to depictions of ânudityâ and âsexual conduct,â and both those terms were specifically and unambiguously defined. See 390 U. S., at 645â647 (Appendix A to opinion of the Court). 4 The California law does not define the term âmaiming,â nor has the State cited any decisions from its courts that define the term in this context. Accordingly, I take the term to have its ordinary meaning, which includes the infliction of any serious wound, see Websterâs Third New International Dictionary 1362 (2002) (hereinafter Websterâs). Cite as: 564 U. S. ____ (2011) 7 ALITO, J., concurring in judgment One of the three elements at issue here refers expressly to âprevailing standards in the community as to what is suitable for minors.â §1746(d)(1)(A)(ii). Another element points in the same direction, asking whether â[a] reason able person, considering [a] game as a whole,â would find that it âappeals to a deviant or morbid interest of minors.â §1746(d)(1)(A)(i) (emphasis added). The terms âdeviantâ and âmorbidâ are not defined in the statute, and California offers no reason to think that its courts would give the terms anything other than their ordinary meaning. See Reply Brief for Petitioners 5 (argu ing that â[a] reasonable person can make this judgment through . . . a common understanding and definition of the applicable termsâ). I therefore assume that âdeviantâ and âmorbidâ carry the meaning that they convey in ordinary speech. The adjective âdeviantâ ordinarily means âdeviat ing . . . from some accepted norm,â and the term âmorbidâ means âof, relating to, or characteristic of disease.â Web sterâs 618, 1469. A âdeviant or morbid interestâ in violence, therefore, appears to be an interest that de viates from what is regardedâpresumably in accordance with some generally accepted standardâas normal and healthy. Thus, the application of the California law is heavily dependent on the identification of generally ac cepted standards regarding the suitability of violent enter tainment for minors. The California Legislature seems to have assumed that these standards are sufficiently well known so that a person of ordinary intelligence would have fair notice as to whether the kind and degree of violence in a particular game is enough to qualify the game as âviolent.â And because the Miller test looks to community standards, the legislature may have thought that the use of undefined community standards in the violent video game law would not present vagueness problems. There is a critical difference, however, between obscen 8 BROWN v. ENTERTAINMENT MERCHANTS ASSN. ALITO, J., concurring in judgment ity laws and laws regulating violence in entertainment. By the time of this Courtâs landmark obscenity cases in the 1960âs, obscenity had long been prohibited, see Roth, 354 U. S., at 484â485, and this experience had helped to shape certain generally accepted norms concerning ex pression related to sex. There is no similar history regarding expression related to violence. As the Court notes, classic literature contains descriptions of great violence, and even childrenâs stories sometimes depict very violent scenes. See ante, at 8â9. Although our society does not generally regard all depic tions of violence as suitable for children or adolescents, the prevalence of violent depictions in childrenâs literature and entertainment creates numerous opportunities for reason able people to disagree about which depictions may excite âdeviantâ or âmorbidâ impulses. See Edwards & Berman, Regulating Violence on Television, 89 Nw. U. L. Rev. 1487, 1523 (1995) (observing that the Miller test would be diffi cult to apply to violent expression because âthere is noth ing even approaching a consensus on low-value violenceâ). Finally, the difficulty of ascertaining the community standards incorporated into the California law is com pounded by the legislatureâs decision to lump all minors together. The California law draws no distinction between young children and adolescents who are nearing the age of majority. In response to a question at oral argument, the attorney defending the constitutionality of the California law said that the State would accept a narrowing construction of the law under which the lawâs references to âminorsâ would be interpreted to refer to the oldest minorsâthat is, those just short of 18. Tr. of Oral Arg. 11â12. However, âit is not within our power to construe and narrow state laws.â Grayned, 408 U. S., at 110. We can only â âextrapo late [their] allowable meaningâ â from the statutory text and authoritative interpretations of similar laws by courts Cite as: 564 U. S. ____ (2011) 9 ALITO, J., concurring in judgment of the State. Ibid. (quoting Garner v. Louisiana, 368 U. S. 157, 174 (1961) (Frankfurter, J., concurring in judgment)). In this case, California has not provided any evidence that the California Legislature intended the law to be limited in this way, or cited any decisions from its courts that would support an âoldest minorsâ construction.5 For these reasons, I conclude that the California violent video game law fails to provide the fair notice that the Constitution requires. And I would go no further. I would not express any view on whether a properly drawn statute would or would not survive First Amendment scrutiny. We should address that question only if and when it is necessary to do so. II Having outlined how I would decide this case, I will now briefly elaborate on my reasons for questioning the wis dom of the Courtâs approach. Some of these reasons are touched upon by the dissents, and while I am not prepared at this time to go as far as either JUSTICE THOMAS or JUSTICE BREYER, they raise valid concerns. A The Court is wrong in saying that the holding in United States v. Stevens, 559 U. S. ___ (2010), âcontrols this case.â Ante, at 4. First, the statute in Stevens differed sharply from the statute at issue here. Stevens struck down a law that broadly prohibited any person from creating, selling, or possessing depictions of animal cruelty for commercial gain. The California law involved here, by contrast, is ââââââ 5 At oral argument, California also proposed that the term âminorsâ could be interpreted as referring to the âtypical age group of minorsâ who play video games. Tr. of Oral Arg. 11. But nothing in the lawâs text supports such a limitation. Nor has California cited any decisions indicating that its courts would restrict the law in this way. And there is nothing in the record indicating what this age group might be. 10 BROWN v. ENTERTAINMENT MERCHANTS ASSN. ALITO, J., concurring in judgment limited to the sale or rental of violent video games to minors. The California law imposes no restriction on the creation of violent video games, or on the possession of such games by anyone, whether above or below the age of 18. The California law does not regulate the sale or rental of violent games by adults. And the California law does not prevent parents and certain other close relatives from buying or renting violent games for their children or other young relatives if they see fit. Second, Stevens does not support the proposition that a law like the one at issue must satisfy strict scrutiny. The portion of Stevens on which the Court relies rejected the Governmentâs contention that depictions of animal cruelty were categorically outside the range of any First Amend ment protection. 559 U. S., at __ (slip op., at 5). Going well beyond Stevens, the Court now holds that any law that attempts to prevent minors from purchasing violent video games must satisfy strict scrutiny instead of the more lenient standard applied in Ginsberg, 390 U. S. 629, our most closely related precedent. As a result of todayâs decision, a State may prohibit the sale to minors of what Ginsberg described as âgirlie magazines,â but a State must surmount a formidable (and perhaps insurmountable) obstacle if it wishes to prevent children from purchasing the most violent and depraved video games imaginable. Third, Stevens expressly left open the possibility that a more narrowly drawn statute targeting depictions of animal cruelty might be compatible with the First Amendment. See 559 U. S., at ___ (slip op., at 19). In this case, the Courtâs sweeping opinion will likely be read by many, both inside and outside the video-game industry, as suggesting that no regulation of minorsâ access to violent video games is allowedâat least without supporting evi dence that may not be realistically obtainable given the nature of the phenomenon in question. Cite as: 564 U. S. ____ (2011) 11 ALITO, J., concurring in judgment B The Courtâs opinion distorts the effect of the California law. I certainly agree with the Court that the government has no âfree-floating power to restrict the ideas to which children may be exposed,â ante, at 7, but the California law does not exercise such a power. If parents want their child to have a violent video game, the California law does not interfere with that parental prerogative. Instead, the California law reinforces parental decisionmaking in exactly the same way as the New York statute upheld in Ginsberg. Under both laws, minors are prevented from purchasing certain materials; and under both laws, par ents are free to supply their children with these items if that is their wish. Citing the video-game industryâs voluntary rating sys tem, the Court argues that the California law does not âmeet a substantial need of parents who wish to restrict their childrenâs access to violent video games but cannot do so.â Ante, at 15. The Court does not mention the fact that the industry adopted this system in response to the threat of federal regulation, Brief for Activision Blizzard, Inc., as Amicus Curiae 7â10, a threat that the Courtâs opinion may now be seen as largely eliminating. Nor does the Court acknowledge that compliance with this system at the time of the enactment of the California law left much to be desired6âor that future enforcement may decline if the video-game industry perceives that any threat of government regulation has vanished. Nor does ââââââ 6A 2004 Federal Trade Commission Report showed that 69 percent of unaccompanied children ages 13 to 16 were able to buy M-rated games and that 56 percent of 13-year-olds were able to buy an M-rated game. Marketing Violent Entertainment to Children: A Fourth Follow-Up Review of Industry Practices in the Motion Picture, Music Recording & Electronic Game Industries 26â28 (July 2004), http://www.ftc.gov/os/ 2004/07/040708kidsviolencerpt.pdf (all Internet materials as visited June 24, 2011, and available in Clerk of Courtâs case file). 12 BROWN v. ENTERTAINMENT MERCHANTS ASSN. ALITO, J., concurring in judgment the Court note, as JUSTICE BREYER points out, see post, at 11 (dissenting opinion), that many parents today are simply not able to monitor their childrenâs use of com puters and gaming devices. C Finally, the Court is far too quick to dismiss the possi bility that the experience of playing video games (and the effects on minors of playing violent video games) may be very different from anything that we have seen before. Any assessment of the experience of playing video games must take into account certain characteristics of the video games that are now on the market and those that are likely to be available in the near future. Todayâs most advanced video games create realistic alternative worlds in which millions of players immerse themselves for hours on end. These games feature visual imagery and sounds that are strikingly realistic, and in the near future video-game graphics may be virtually indistinguishable from actual video footage.7 Many of the games already on the market can produce high definition images,8 and it is predicted that it will not be long before video-game images will be seen in three dimensions.9 It is also forecast that video games will soon provide sensory ââââââ 7 See Chayka, Visual Games: Photorealism in Crisis, Kill Screen (May 2011), http://killscreendaily.com/articles/visual-games-photorealism-crisis. 8 To see brief video excerpts from games with highly realistic graph ics, see Spike TV Video Game Awards 2010âGame of the Year Nomi nees, GameTrailers.com (Dec. 10, 2010), http://www.gametrailers.com/ video/game-of-spike-tv-vga/707755?type=flv. 9 See Selleck, Sony PS3 Launching 50 3D-Capable Video Games in the Near Future, SlashGear (Nov. 23, 2010), http://www.slashgear.com/ sony-ps3-launching-50-3d-capable-video-games-in-the-near-future-23115866; Sofge, Why 3D Doesnât Work for TV, But Is Great for Gaming, Popu- lar Mechanics (Mar. 11, 2010), http://www.popularmechanics.com/ technology/digital/gaming/4342437. Cite as: 564 U. S. ____ (2011) 13 ALITO, J., concurring in judgment feedback.10 By wearing a special vest or other device, a player will be able to experience physical sensations sup posedly felt by a character on the screen.11 Some amici who support respondents foresee the day when â âvirtual reality shoot-âem-upsâ â will allow children to â âactually feel the splatting blood from the blown-off headâ â of a victim. Brief for Reporters Comm. for Freedom of the Press et al. as Amici Curiae 29 (quoting H. Schechter, Savage Pas times 18 (2005)). Persons who play video games also have an unprece dented ability to participate in the events that take place in the virtual worlds that these games create. Players can create their own video-game characters and can use pho tos to produce characters that closely resemble actual people. A person playing a sophisticated game can make a multitude of choices and can thereby alter the course of the action in the game. In addition, the means by which players control the action in video games now bear a closer relationship to the means by which people control action in the real world. While the action in older games was often directed with buttons or a joystick, players dictate the action in newer games by engaging in the same mo ââââââ 10 T. Chatfield, Fun Inc.: Why Games are the Twenty-first Centuryâs Most Serious Business 211 (2010) (predicting that â[w]e can expect . . . physical feedback and motion detection as standard in every gaming device in the near futureâ); J. Blascovich & J. Bailenson, Infinite Reality: Avatars, Eternal Life, New Worlds, and the Dawn of the Virtual Revolution 2 (2011) (âTechnological developments powering virtual worlds are accelerating, ensuring that virtual experiences will become more immersive by providing sensory information that makes people feel they are âinsideâ virtual worldsâ (emphasis in the original)). 11 See Topolsky, The Mindwire V5 Turns Gaming into Pure Electro shock Torture, Engadget (Mar. 9, 2008), http://www.engadget.com/ 2008/03/09/the-mindwire-v5-turns-gaming-into-pure-electroshock-torture; Greenemeier, Video Game Vest Simulates Sensation of Being Capped, Scientific American (Oct. 25, 2007), http://www.scientificamerican.com/ article.cfm?id=video-game-vest-simulates. 14 BROWN v. ENTERTAINMENT MERCHANTS ASSN. ALITO, J., concurring in judgment tions that they desire a character in the game to per form.12 For example, a player who wants a video-game character to swing a baseball batâeither to hit a ball or smash a skullâcould bring that about by simulating the motion of actually swinging a bat. These present-day and emerging characteristics of video games must be considered together with characteristics of the violent games that have already been marketed. In some of these games, the violence is astounding.13 Victims by the dozens are killed with every imaginable implement, including machine guns, shotguns, clubs, hammers, axes, swords, and chainsaws. Victims are dismembered, decapitated, disemboweled, set on fire, and chopped into little pieces. They cry out in agony and beg for mercy. Blood gushes, splatters, and pools. Severed body parts and gobs of human remains are graphically shown. In some games, points are awarded based, not only on the number of victims killed, but on the killing technique employed. It also appears that there is no antisocial theme too base for some in the video-game industry to exploit. There are games in which a player can take on the identity and reenact the killings carried out by the perpetrators of the murders at Columbine High School and Virginia Tech.14 ââââââ 12 See Schiesel, A Real Threat Now Faces the Nintendo Wii, N. Y. Times, Dec. 3, 2010, p. F7 (describing how leading developers of video game consoles are competing to deliver gesture-controlled gaming devices). 13 For a sample of violent video games, see Wilson, The 10 Most Violent Video Games of All Time, PCMag.com (Feb. 10, 2011), http://www.pcmag.com/article2/0,2817,2379959,00.asp. To see brief video excerpts from violent games, see Chomik, Top 10: Most Violent Video Games, AskMen.com, http://www.askmen.com/top_10/videogame/ top-10-most-violent-video-games.html; Sayed, 15 Most Violent Video Games That Made You Puke, Gamingbolt (May 2, 2010), http:// gamingbolt.com/15-most-violent-video-games-that-made-you-puke. 14 Webley, âSchool Shooterâ Video Game to Reenact Columbine, Vir Cite as: 564 U. S. ____ (2011) 15 ALITO, J., concurring in judgment The objective of one game is to rape a mother and her daughters;15 in another, the goal is to rape Native Ameri can women.16 There is a game in which players engage in âethnic cleansingâ and can choose to gun down African- Americans, Latinos, or Jews.17 In still another game, players attempt to fire a rifle shot into the head of Presi dent Kennedy as his motorcade passes by the Texas School Book Depository.18 If the technological characteristics of the sophisticated games that are likely to be available in the near future are combined with the characteristics of the most violent games already marketed, the result will be games that allow troubled teens to experience in an extraordinarily personal and vivid way what it would be like to carry out unspeakable acts of violence. The Court is untroubled by this possibility. According to the Court, the âinteractiveâ nature of video games is ânoth ing newâ because âall literature is interactive.â Ante, at 10â11. Disagreeing with this assessment, the Interna tional Game Developers Association (IGDA)âa group that presumably understands the nature of video games and that supports respondentsâtells us that video games are ââââââ ginia Tech Killings, Time (Apr. 20, 2011), http://newsfeed.time.com/ 2011/04/20/school-shooter-video-game-reenacts-columbine-virginia-tech killings. After a Web site that made School Shooter available for download removed it in response to mounting criticism, the developer stated that it may make the game available on its own Web site. Inside the Sick Site of a School Shooter Mod (Mar. 26, 2011), http://ssnat.com. 15 Lah, âRapeLayâ Video Game Goes Viral Amid Outrage, CNN (Mar. 30, 2010), http://articles.cnn.com/2010-03-30/world/japan.video. game.rape_1_game-teenage-girl-japanese-government?_s=PM:WORLD. 16 Graham, Custer May be Shot Down Again in a Battle of the Sexes Over X-Rated Video Games, People, Nov. 15, 1982, pp. 110, 115. 17 Scheeres, Games Elevate Hate to Next Level, Wired (Feb. 20, 2002), http://www.wired.com/culture/lifestyle/news/2002/02/50523. 18 Thompson, A View to a Kill: JFK Reloaded is Just Plain Creepy, Slate (Nov. 22, 2004), http://www.slate.com/id/2110034. 16 BROWN v. ENTERTAINMENT MERCHANTS ASSN. ALITO, J., concurring in judgment âfar more concretely interactive.â Brief for IGDA et al. as Amici Curiae 3. And on this point, the game developers are surely correct. It is certainly true, as the Court notes, that â â[l]it erature, when it is successful draws the reader into the story, makes him identify with the characters, invites him to judge them and quarrel with them, to experience their joys and sufferings as the readerâs own.â â Ante, at 11 (quoting American Amusement Machine Assn. v. Kendrick, 244 F. 3d 572, 577 (CA7 2001)). But only an extraordinar ily imaginative reader who reads a description of a killing in a literary work will experience that event as vividly as he might if he played the role of the killer in a video game. To take an example, think of a person who reads the passage in Crime and Punishment in which Raskolni- kov kills the old pawn broker with an axe. See F. Dostoyevsky, Crime and Punishment 78 (Modern Library ed. 1950). Compare that reader with a video-game player who creates an avatar that bears his own image; who sees a realistic image of the victim and the scene of the killing in high definition and in three dimensions; who is forced to decide whether or not to kill the victim and decides to do so; who then pretends to grasp an axe, to raise it above the head of the victim, and then to bring it down; who hears the thud of the axe hitting her head and her cry of pain; who sees her split skull and feels the sensation of blood on his face and hands. For most people, the two experiences will not be the same.19 When all of the characteristics of video games are taken into account, there is certainly a reasonable basis for ââââââ 19 As the Court notes, there are a few childrenâs books that ask young readers to step into the shoes of a character and to make choices that take the stories along one of a very limited number of possible lines. See ante, at 10. But the very nature of the print medium makes it impossible for a book to offer anything like the same number of choices as those provided by a video game. Cite as: 564 U. S. ____ (2011) 17 ALITO, J., concurring in judgment thinking that the experience of playing a video game may be quite different from the experience of reading a book, listening to a radio broadcast, or viewing a movie. And if this is so, then for at least some minors, the effects of playing violent video games may also be quite different. The Court acts prematurely in dismissing this possibility out of hand. * * * For all these reasons, I would hold only that the particu lar law at issue here fails to provide the clear notice that the Constitution requires. I would not squelch legislative efforts to deal with what is perceived by some to be a significant and developing social problem. If differently framed statutes are enacted by the States or by the Fed eral Government, we can consider the constitutionality of those laws when cases challenging them are presented to us. Cite as: 564 U. S. ____ (2011) 1 THOMAS, J., dissenting SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES _________________ No. 08â1448 _________________ EDMUND G. BROWN, JR., GOVERNOR OF CAL- IFORNIA, ET AL., PETITIONERS v. ENTERTAIN- MENT MERCHANTS ASSOCIATION ET AL. ON WRIT OF CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE NINTH CIRCUIT [June 27, 2011] JUSTICE THOMAS, dissenting. The Courtâs decision today does not comport with the original public understanding of the First Amendment. The majority strikes down, as facially unconstitutional, a state law that prohibits the direct sale or rental of certain video games to minors because the law âabridg[es] the freedom of speech.â U. S. Const., Amdt. 1. But I do not think the First Amendment stretches that far. The prac tices and beliefs of the founding generation establish that âthe freedom of speech,â as originally understood, does not include a right to speak to minors (or a right of minors to access speech) without going through the minorsâ parents or guardians. I would hold that the law at issue is not facially unconstitutional under the First Amendment, and reverse and remand for further proceedings.1 ââââââ 1 JUSTICE ALITO concludes that the law is too vague to satisfy due process, but neither the District Court nor the Court of Appeals ad dressed that question. Ante, at 2â9 (opinion concurring in judgment). As we have often said, this Court is âone of final review, ânot of first view.â â FCC v. Fox Television Stations, Inc., 556 U. S. ___, ___ (2009) (slip op., at 25) (quoting Cutter v. Wilkinson, 544 U. S. 709, 718, n. 7 (2005)). 2 BROWN v. ENTERTAINMENT MERCHANTS ASSN. THOMAS, J., dissenting I When interpreting a constitutional provision, âthe goal is to discern the most likely public understanding of [that] provision at the time it was adopted.â McDonald v. Chi cago, 561 U. S. ___, ___ (2010) (slip op., at 25) (THOMAS, J., concurring in part and concurring in judgment). Because the Constitution is a written instrument, âits meaning does not alter.â McIntyre v. Ohio Elections Commân, 514 U. S. 334, 359 (1995) (THOMAS, J., concurring in judgment) (internal quotation marks omitted). âThat which it meant when adopted, it means now.â Ibid. (internal quotation marks omitted). As originally understood, the First Amendmentâs protec tion against laws âabridging the freedom of speechâ did not extend to all speech. âThere are certain well-defined and narrowly limited classes of speech, the prevention and punishment of which have never been thought to raise any Constitutional problem.â Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, 315 U. S. 568, 571â572 (1942); see also United States v. Stevens, 559 U. S. ___, ___ (2010) (slip op., at 5â6). Laws regulating such speech do not âabridg[e] the freedom of speechâ because such speech is understood to fall outside âthe freedom of speech.â See Ashcroft v. Free Speech Coa lition, 535 U. S. 234, 245â246 (2002). In my view, the âpractices and beliefs held by the Foun dersâ reveal another category of excluded speech: speech to minor children bypassing their parents. McIntyre, supra, at 360. The historical evidence shows that the founding generation believed parents had absolute authority over their minor children and expected parents to use that authority to direct the proper development of their chil dren. It would be absurd to suggest that such a society understood âthe freedom of speechâ to include a right to speak to minors (or a corresponding right of minors to access speech) without going through the minorsâ parents. Cf. Brief for Common Sense Media as Amicus Curiae 12â Cite as: 564 U. S. ____ (2011) 3 THOMAS, J., dissenting 15. The founding generation would not have considered it an abridgment of âthe freedom of speechâ to support parental authority by restricting speech that bypasses minorsâ parents. A Attitudes toward children were in a state of transition around the time that the States ratified the Bill of Rights. A complete understanding of the founding generationâs views on children and the parent-child relationship must therefore begin roughly a century earlier, in colonial New England. In the Puritan tradition common in the New England Colonies, fathers ruled families with absolute authority. âThe patriarchal family was the basic building block of Puritan society.â S. Mintz, Huckâs Raft 13 (2004) (herein after Mintz); see also R. MacDonald, Literature for Chil dren in England and America from 1646 to 1774, p. 7 (1982) (hereinafter MacDonald). The Puritans rejected many customs, such as godparenthood, that they consid ered inconsistent with the patriarchal structure. Mintz 13. Part of the fatherâs absolute power was the right and duty âto fill his childrenâs minds with knowledge and . . . make them apply their knowledge in right action.â E. Morgan, The Puritan Family 97 (rev. ed. 1966) (herein after Morgan). Puritans thought children were âinnately sinful and that parentsâ primary task was to suppress their childrenâs natural depravity.â S. Mintz & S. Kellogg, Domestic Revolutions 2 (1988) (hereinafter Mintz & Kel logg); see also B. Wadsworth, The Well-Ordered Family 55 (1712) (âChildren should not be left to themselves . . . to do as they please; . . . not being fit to govern themselvesâ); C. Mather, A Family Well-Ordered 38 (1699). Accordingly, parents were not to let their children read âvain Books, profane Ballads, and filthy Songsâ or âfond and amorous 4 BROWN v. ENTERTAINMENT MERCHANTS ASSN. THOMAS, J., dissenting Romances, . . . fabulous Histories of Giants, the bom- bast Achievements of Knight Errantry, and the like.â The History of Genesis, pp. viâvii (3d ed. corrected 1708). This conception of parental authority was reflected in laws at that time. In the Massachusetts Colony, for example, it was unlawful for tavern keepers (or anyone else) to entertain children without their parentsâ consent. 2 Records and Files of the Quarterly Courts of Essex County, Massachusetts, p. 180 (1912); 4 id., at 237, 275 (1914); 5 id., at 143 (1916); see also Morgan 146. And a âstubborn or rebellious sonâ of 16 years or more committed a capital offense if he disobeyed âthe voice of his Father, or the voice of his Mother.â The Laws and Liberties of Mas sachusetts 6 (1648) (reprint M. Farrand ed. 1929); see also J. Kamensky, Governing the Tongue 102, n. 14 (1997) (citing similar laws in the Connecticut, New Haven, Ply mouth, and New Hampshire Colonies in the late 1600âs). B In the decades leading up to and following the Revolu tion, attitudes towards children changed. See, e.g., J. Reinier, From Virtue to Character: American Childhood, 1775â1850, p. 1 (1996) (hereinafter Reinier). Children came to be seen less as innately sinful and more as blank slates requiring careful and deliberate development. But the same overarching principles remained. Parents con tinued to have both the right and duty to ensure the proper development of their children. They exercised significant authority over their children, including control over the books that children read. And laws at the time continued to reflect strong support for parental author- ity and the sense that children were not fit to govern themselves. 1 The works of John Locke and Jean-Jacques Rousseau Cite as: 564 U. S. ____ (2011) 5 THOMAS, J., dissenting were a driving force behind the changed understanding of children and childhood. See Reinier 2â5; H. Brewer, By Birth or Consent 97 (2005) (hereinafter Brewer); K. Cal vert, Children in the House 59â60 (1992) (hereinafter Calvert). Locke taught that childrenâs minds were blank slates and that parents therefore had to be careful and deliberate about what their children were told and ob served. Parents had only themselves to blame if, âby hu mouring and cockeringâ their children, they âpoisonâd the fountainâ and later âtaste[d] the bitter waters.â Some Thoughts Concerning Education (1692), in 37 English Philosophers of the Seventeenth and Eighteenth Centuries 27â28 (C. Eliot ed. 1910). All vices, he explained, were sowed by parents and âthose about children.â Id., at 29. Significantly, Locke did not suggest circumscribing paren tal authority but rather articulated a new basis for it. Rousseau disagreed with Locke in important respects, but his philosophy was similarly premised on parental control over a childâs development. Although Rousseau advocated that children should be allowed to develop naturally, he instructed that the environment be directed by âa tutor who is given total control over the child and who removes him from society, from all competing sources of authority and influence.â J. Fliegelman, Prodigals and Pilgrims 30 (1982) (hereinafter Fliegelman); see also Reinier 15. These writings received considerable attention in Amer ica. Lockeâs An Essay Concerning Human Understanding and his Some Thoughts Concerning Education were sig nificantly more popular than his Two Treatises of Gov ernment, according to a study of 92 colonial libraries between 1700 and 1776. Lundberg & May, The Enlight ened Reader in America, 28 American Quarterly 262, 273 (1976) (hereinafter Lundberg). And Rousseauâs Emile, a treatise on education, was more widely advertised and distributed than his political work, The Social Contract. Fliegelman 29; see also Lundberg 285. In general, the 6 BROWN v. ENTERTAINMENT MERCHANTS ASSN. THOMAS, J., dissenting most popular books in the Colonies on the eve of the American Revolution were not political discourses but ones concerned with child rearing. See Mintz & Kellogg 45. 2 Lockeâs and Rousseauâs writings fostered a new concep tion of childhood. Children were increasingly viewed as malleable creatures, and childhood came to be seen as an important period of growth, development, and preparation for adulthood. See Mintz & Kellogg 17, 21, 47; M. Gross berg, Governing the Hearth 8 (1985) (hereinafter Gross berg). Noah Webster, called the father of American educa tion, wrote that â[t]he impressions received in early life usually form the characters of individuals.â On the Edu cation of Youth in America (1790) (hereinafter Webster), in Essays on Education in the Early Republic 43 (F. Ru dolph ed. 1965) (hereinafter Rudolph); cf. Slater, Noah Webster: Founding Father of American Scholarship and Education, in Noah Websterâs First Edition of an Ameri can Dictionary of the English Language (1967). Elizabeth Smith, sister-in-law to John Adams, similarly wrote: âThe Infant Mind, I beleive[,] is a blank, that eassily receives any impression.â M. Norton, Libertyâs Daughters 101 (1996) (internal quotation marks omitted) (hereinafter Norton); see also S. Doggett, A Discourse on Education (1796) (hereinafter Doggett), in Rudolph 151 (â[I]n early youth, . . . every power and capacity is pliable and suscep tible of any direction or impressionâ); J. Abbott, The Mother at Home 2 (1834) (hereinafter Abbott) (âWhat impressions can be more strong, and more lasting, than those received upon the mind in the freshness and the susceptibility of youthâ). Children lacked reason and decisionmaking ability. They âhave not Judgment or Will of their own,â John Adams noted. Letter to James Sullivan (May 26, 1776), in Cite as: 564 U. S. ____ (2011) 7 THOMAS, J., dissenting 4 Papers of John Adams 210 (R. Taylor ed. 1979); see also Vol. 1 1787: Drafting the Constitution, p. 229 (W. Benton ed. 1986) (quoting Gouvernor Morris in James Madisonâs notes from the Constitutional Convention explaining that children do not vote because they âwant prudenceâ and âhave no will of their ownâ). Childrenâs âutter incapacityâ rendered them âalmost wholly at the mercy of their Par ents or Instructors for a set of habits to regulate their whole conduct through life.â J. Burgh, Thoughts on Edu cation 7 (1749) (hereinafter Burgh). This conception of childhood led to great concern about influences on children. âYouth are ever learning to do what they see others around them doing, and these imita tions grow into habits.â Doggett, in Rudolph 151; see also B. Rush, A Plan for the Establishment of Public Schools (1786) (hereinafter Rush), in Rudolph 16 (âThe vices of young people are generally learned from each otherâ); Webster, in Rudolph 58 (â[C]hildren, artless and unsus pecting, resign their hearts to any person whose manners are agreeable and whose conduct is respectableâ). Books therefore advised parents ânot to put children in the way of those whom you dare not trust.â L. Child, The Motherâs Book 149 (1831) (hereinafter Child); see also S. Coontz, The Social Origins of Private Life 149â150 (1988) (noting that it was âconsidered dangerous to leave children to the supervision of servants or apprenticesâ). As a result, it was widely accepted that children needed close monitoring and carefully planned development. See B. Wishy, The Child and the Republic 24â25, 32 (1968) (hereinafter Wishy); Grossberg 8. Managing the young mind was considered âinfinitely important.â Doggett, in Rudolph 151; see also A. MacLeod, A Moral Tale 72â73 (1975) (hereinafter MacLeod). In an essay on the educa tion of youth in America, Noah Webster described the human mind as âa rich field, which, without constant care, will ever be covered with a luxuriant growth of weeds.â 8 BROWN v. ENTERTAINMENT MERCHANTS ASSN. THOMAS, J., dissenting Rudolph 54. He advocated sheltering children from âevery low-bred, drunken, immoral characterâ and keeping their minds âuntainted till their reasoning faculties have ac quired strength and the good principles which may be planted in their minds have taken deep root.â Id., at 63; see also Rush, in id., at 16 (â[T]he most useful citizens have been formed from those youth who have never known or felt their own wills till they were one and twenty years of ageâ); Burgh 7 (â[T]he souls of Youth are more immedi ately committed to the care of Parents and Instructors than even those of a People are to their Pastorâ). The Revolution only amplified these concerns. The Re public would require virtuous citizens, which necessi- tated proper training from childhood. See Mintz 54, 71; MacLeod 40; Saxton, French and American Childhoods, in Children and Youth in a New Nation 69 (J. Marten ed. 2009) (hereinafter Marten); see also W. Cardell, Story of Jack Halyard, pp. xvâxvi (30th ed. 1834) (hereinafter Cardell) (â[T]he glory and efficacy of our institutions will soon rest with those who are growing up to succede usâ). Children were âthe pivot of the moral world,â and their proper development was âa subject of as high interest, as any to which the human mind ha[d] ever been called.â Id., at xvi. 3 Based on these views of childhood, the founding genera tion understood parents to have a right and duty to govern their childrenâs growth. Parents were expected to direct the development and education of their children and en sure that bad habits did not take root. See Calvert 58â59; MacLeod 72; Mintz & Kellogg 23. They were responsible for instilling âmoral prohibitions, behavioral standards, and a capacity for self-government that would prepare a child for the outside world.â Mintz & Kellogg 58; see also Youthâs Companion, Apr. 16, 1827, p. 1 (hereinafter Cite as: 564 U. S. ____ (2011) 9 THOMAS, J., dissenting Youthâs Companion) (âLet [childrenâs] minds be formed, their hearts prepared, and their characters moulded for the scenes and the duties of a brighter dayâ). In short, â[h]ome and family bore the major responsibility for the moral training of children and thus, by implication, for the moral health of the nation.â MacLeod 29; see also Intro duction, in Marten 6; Reinier, p. xi; Smith, Autonomy and Affection: Parents and Children in Eighteenth-Century Chesapeake Families, in Growing up in America 54 (N. Hiner & J. Hawes eds. 1985). This conception of parental rights and duties was exem plified by Thomas Jeffersonâs approach to raising children. He wrote letters to his daughters constantly and often gave specific instructions about what the children should do. See, e.g., Letter to Martha Jefferson (Nov. 28, 1783), in S. Randolph, The Domestic Life of Thomas Jefferson 44 (1939) (dictating her daily schedule of music, dancing, drawing, and studying); Letter to Martha Jefferson (Dec. 22, 1783), in id., at 45â46 (âI do not wish you to be gaily clothed at this time of life . . . . [A]bove all things and at all times let your clothes be neat, whole, and properly put onâ). Jefferson expected his daughter, Martha, to write âby every postâ and instructed her, âInform me what books you read [and] what tunes you learn.â Letter (Nov. 28, 1783), in id., at 44. He took the same approach with his nephew, Peter Carr, after Carrâs father died. See Letter (Aug. 19, 1785), in 8 The Papers of Thomas Jefferson 405â 408 (J. Boyd ed. 1953) (detailing a course of reading and exercise, and asking for monthly progress reports describ ing âin what manner you employ every hour in the dayâ); see also 3 Dictionary of Virginia Biography 29 (2006). Jeffersonâs rigorous management of his charges was not uncommon. â[M]uch evidence indicates that mothers and fathers both believed in giving their children a strict up bringing, enforcing obedience to their commands and stressing continued subjection to the parental will.â Nor 10 BROWN v. ENTERTAINMENT MERCHANTS ASSN. THOMAS, J., dissenting ton 96. Two parenting books published in the 1830âs gave prototypical advice. In The Motherâs Book, Lydia Child advised that â[t]he first and most important step in man agement is, that whatever a mother says, always must be done.â Child 26. John Abbott, the author of The Mother at Home, likewise advised that â[o]bedience is absolutely essential to proper family government.â Abbott 18. Echo ing Locke, Abbott warned that parents who indulged a childâs âfoolish and unreasonable wishesâ would doom that child to be indulgent in adulthood. Id., at 16. The concept of total parental control over childrenâs lives extended into the schools. âThe government both of fami lies and schools should be absolute,â declared Noah Web ster. Rudolph 57â58. Dr. Benjamin Rush concurred: âIn the education of youth, let the authority of our masters be as absolute as possible.â Id., at 16. Through the doctrine of in loco parentis, teachers assumed the â âsacred dut[y] of parents . . . to train up and qualify their childrenâ â and exercised the same authority â âto command obedience, to control stubbornness, to quicken diligence, and to reform bad habits.â â Morse v. Frederick, 551 U. S. 393, 413â414 (2007) (THOMAS, J., concurring) (quoting State v. Pender grass, 19 N. C. 365, 365â366 (1837)); see also Wishy 73. Thus, the quality of teachers and schools had to âbe watched with the most scrupulous attention.â Webster, in Rudolph 64. For their part, children were expected to be dutiful and obedient. Mintz & Kellogg 53; Wishy 31; cf. J. Kett, Rites of Passage 45 (1977). Schoolbooks instructed children to do so and frequently featured vignettes illustrating the consequences of disobedience. See Adams, âPictures of the Vicious ultimately overcome by misery and shameâ: The Cultural Work of Early National Schoolbooks (hereinafter Adams), in Marten 156. One oft-related example was the hangings of 19 alleged witches in 1692, which, the school books noted, likely began with false complaints by two Cite as: 564 U. S. ____ (2011) 11 THOMAS, J., dissenting young girls. See J. Morse, The American Geography 191 (1789); see also Adams, in Marten 164. An entire genre of books, âloosely termed âadvice to youth,â â taught similar lessons well into the 1800âs. J. Demos, Circles and Lines: The Shape of Life in Early America 73 (2004); cf. Wishy 54. âNext to your duty to God,â advised one book, âis your duty to your parentsâ even if the child did not âunderstand the reason of their commands.â L. Sigourney, The Girlâs Reading Book 44 (14th ed. 1843); see also Filial Duty Recommended and Enforced, Introduction, p. iii (c. 1798); The Parentâs Pre sent 44 (3d ed. 1841). âDisobedience is generally punished in some way or other,â warned another, âand often very severely.â S. Goodrich, Peter Parleyâs Book of Fables 43 (1836); see also The Country School-House 27 (1848) (â[T]he number of children who die from the effects of disobedience to their parents is very largeâ). 4 Societyâs concern with childrenâs development extended to the books they read. âVice always spreads by being published,â Noah Webster observed. Rudolph 62. â[Y]oung people are taught many vices by fiction, books, or pub- lic exhibitions, vices which they never would have known had they never read such books or attended such pub- lic places.â Ibid.; see also Cardell, p. xii (cautioning par ents that â[t]he first reading lessons for children have an extensive influence on the acquisitions and habits of future yearsâ); Youthâs Companion 1 (â[T]he capacities of children, and the peculiar situation and duties of youth, require select and appropriate readingâ). Prominent childrenâs authors harshly criticized fairy tales and the use of anthropomorphic animals. See, e.g., S. Goodrich, 2 Recollections of a Lifetime 320, n.* (1856) (describing fairy tales as âcalculated to familiarize the mind with things shocking and monstrous; to cultivate a taste for tales of 12 BROWN v. ENTERTAINMENT MERCHANTS ASSN. THOMAS, J., dissenting bloodshed and violence; to teach the young to use coarse language, and cherish vulgar ideas; . . . and to fill [the youthful mind] with the horrors of a debased and de bauched fancyâ); 1 id., at 167 (recalling that childrenâs books were âfull of nonsenseâ and âliesâ); Cardell, p. xiv (âThe fancy of converting inferior animals into âteachers of children,â has been carried to ridiculous extravaganceâ); see also MacDonald 83, 103 (noting that fables and works of fantasy were not popular in America in the 1700âs). Adults carefully controlled what they published for children. Stories written for children were dedicated to moral instruction and were relatively austere, lacking details that might titillate childrenâs minds. See MacLeod 24â25, 42â48; see also id., at 42 (âThe authors of juvenile fiction imposed the constraints upon themselves in the name of duty, and for the sake of giving children what they thought children should have, although they were often well aware that children might prefer more excit ing fareâ); Francis, American Childrenâs Literature, 1646â1880, in American Childhood 208â209 (J. Hawes & N. Hiner eds. 1985). John Newbery, the publisher often credited with creating the genre of childrenâs literature, removed traditional folk characters, like Tom Thumb, from their original stories and placed them in new moral ity tales in which good children were rewarded and dis obedient children punished. Reinier 12. Parents had total authority over what their children read. See A. MacLeod, American Childhood 177 (1994) (âIdeally, if not always actually, nineteenth-century par ents regulated their childrenâs lives fully, certainly includ ing their readingâ). Lydia Child put it bluntly in The Motherâs Book: âChildren . . . should not read anything without a motherâs knowledge and sanction; this is par ticularly necessary between the ages of twelve and six teen.â Child 92; see also id., at 143 (â[P]arents, or some guardian friends, should carefully examine every volume Cite as: 564 U. S. ____ (2011) 13 THOMAS, J., dissenting they put into the hands of young peopleâ); E. Monaghan, Learning to Read and Write in Colonial America 337 (2005) (reviewing a 12-year-old girlâs journal from the early 1770âs and noting that the childâs aunts monitored and guided her reading). 5 The law at the time reflected the founding generationâs understanding of parent-child relations. According to Sir William Blackstone, parents were responsible for main taining, protecting, and education their children, and therefore had âpowerâ over their children. 1 Commentar ies on the Laws of England 434, 440 (1765); cf. Washington v. Glucksberg, 521 U. S. 702, 712 (1997) (Blackstoneâs Commentaries was âa primary legal authority for 18th- and 19th-century American lawyersâ). Chancellor James Kent agreed. 2 Commentaries on American Law *189â *207. The law entitled parents to âthe custody of their [children],â âthe value of th[e] [childrenâs] labor and ser vices,â and the âright to the exercise of such discipline as may be requisite for the discharge of their sacred trust.â Id., at *193, *203. Children, in turn, were charged with âobedience and assistance during their own minority, and gratitude and reverance during the rest of their lives.â Id., at *207. Thus, in case after case, courts made clear that parents had a right to the childâs labor and services until the child reached majority. In 1810, the Supreme Judicial Court of Massachusetts explained, âThere is no question but that a father, who is entitled to the services of his minor son, and for whom he is obliged to provide, may, at the common law, assign those services to others, for a consideration to enure to himself.â Day v. Everett,
7 Mass. 145
, 147; see also Benson v. Remington,
2 Mass. 113
, 115 (1806) (opin ion of Parsons, C. J.) (âThe law is very well settled, that parents are under obligations to support their children, 14 BROWN v. ENTERTAINMENT MERCHANTS ASSN. THOMAS, J., dissenting and that they are entitled to their earningsâ). Similarly, the Supreme Court of Judicature of New Hampshire noted that the right of parents to recover for the services of their child, while a minor, âcannot be contested.â Gale v. Parrot, 1 N. H. 28, 29 (1817). And parents could bring tort suits against those who knowingly enticed a minor away from them. See, e.g., Kirkpatrick v. Lockhart,
2 Brev. 276
(S. C. Constitutional Ct. 1809); Jones v. Tevis,
4 Litt. 25
(Ky. App. 1823). Relatedly, boys could not enlist in the military without parental consent. Many of those who did so during the Revolutionary War found, afterwards, that their fathers were entitled to their military wages. See Cox, Boy Sol diers of the American Revolution, in Marten 21â24. And after the war, minors who enlisted without parental con sent in violation of federal law could find themselves returned home on writs of habeas corpus issued at their parentsâ request. See, e.g., United States v. Anderson,
24
F. Cas. 813
(No. 14,449) (CC Tenn. 1812); Commonwealth v. Callan,
6 Binn. 255
(Pa. 1814) (per curiam). Laws also set age limits restricting marriage without parental consent. For example, from 1730 until at least 1849, Pennsylvania law required parental consent for the marriage of anyone under the age of 21. See 4 Statutes at Large of Pennsylvania 153 (J. Mitchell & H. Flanders eds. 1897) (hereinafter Pa. Stats. at Large); General Laws of Pennsylvania 82â83 (J. Dunlop 2d ed. 1849) (including the 1730 marriage law with no amendments); see also Perpet ual Laws of the Commonwealth of Massachusetts 253 (1788), in The First Laws of the Commonwealth of Massa chusetts (J. Cushing ed. 1981). In general, â[p]ost- Revolutionary marriage law assumed that below a certain age, children could . . . no[t] intellectually understand its significance.â Grossberg 105. Indeed, the law imposed age limits on all manner of activities that required judgment and reason. Children Cite as: 564 U. S. ____ (2011) 15 THOMAS, J., dissenting could not vote, could not serve on juries, and generally could not be witnesses in criminal cases unless they were older than 14. See Brewer 43, 145, 148, 159. Nor could they swear loyalty to a State. See, e.g., 9 Pa. Stats. at Large 111 (1903 ed.). Early federal laws granting aliens the ability to become citizens provided that those under 21 were deemed citizens if their fathers chose to naturalize. See, e.g., Act of Mar. 26, 1790, 1 Stat. 104; Act of Jan. 29, 1795, ch. 20, 1 Stat. 415. C The history clearly shows a founding generation that believed parents to have complete authority over their minor children and expected parents to direct the devel opment of those children. The Puritan tradition in New England laid the foundation of American parental author ity and duty. See MacDonald 6 (âThe Puritans are virtu ally the inventors of the family as we know it todayâ). In the decades leading up to and following the Revolution, the conception of the childâs mind evolved but the duty and authority of parents remained. Indeed, society paid closer attention to potential influences on children than before. See Mintz 72 (âBy weakening earlier forms of patriarchal authority, the Revolution enhanced the importance of childrearing and education in ensuring social stabilityâ). Teachers and schools came under scrutiny, and childrenâs reading material was carefully supervised. Laws reflected these concerns and often supported parental authority with the coercive power of the state. II A In light of this history, the Framers could not possibly have understood âthe freedom of speechâ to include an unqualified right to speak to minors. Specifically, I am sure that the founding generation would not have under 16 BROWN v. ENTERTAINMENT MERCHANTS ASSN. THOMAS, J., dissenting stood âthe freedom of speechâ to include a right to speak to children without going through their parents. As a conse quence, I do not believe that laws limiting such speechâ for example, by requiring parental consent to speak to a minorââabridg[e] the freedom of speechâ within the origi nal meaning of the First Amendment. We have recently noted that this Court does not have âfreewheeling authority to declare new categories of speech outside the scope of the First Amendment.â Ste vens, 559 U. S., at ___ (slip op., at 9). But we also recog nized that there may be âsome categories of speech that have been historically unprotected [and] have not yet been specifically identified or discussed as such in our case law.â Ibid. In my opinion, the historical evidence here plainly reveals one such category.2 B Admittedly, the original public understanding of a constitutional provision does not always comport with modern sensibilities. See Morse, 551 U. S., at 419 (THOMAS, J., concurring) (treating students âas though it ââââââ 2 The majority responds that âit does not followâ from the historical evidence âthat the state has the power to prevent children from hearing . . . anything without their parentsâ prior consent.â Ante, at 7, n. 3. Such a conclusion, the majority asserts, would lead to laws that, in its view, would be undesirable and âobviouslyâ unconstitutional. Ibid. The majorityâs circular argument misses the point. The question is not whether certain laws might make sense to judges or legislators today, but rather what the public likely understood âthe freedom of speechâ to mean when the First Amendment was adopted. See District of Columbia v. Heller, 554 U. S. 570, 634â635 (2008). I believe it is clear that the founding public would not have understood âthe freedom of speechâ to include speech to minor children bypassing their parents. It follows that the First Amendment imposes no restriction on state regulation of such speech. To note that there may not be âprecedent for [such] state control,â ante, at 8, n. 3, âis not to establish that [there] is a constitutional right,â McIntyre v. Ohio Elections Commân, 514 U. S. 334, 373 (1995) (SCALIA, J., dissenting). Cite as: 564 U. S. ____ (2011) 17 THOMAS, J., dissenting were still the 19th century would find little support to dayâ). It may also be inconsistent with precedent. See McDonald, 561 U. S., at ___â___ (THOMAS, J., concurring in part and concurring in judgment) (slip op., at 48â 52) (rejecting the Slaughter-House Cases,
16 Wall. 36
(1873), as inconsistent with the original public meaning of the Privileges or Immunities Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment). This, however, is not such a case. Although much has changed in this country since the Revolution, the notion that parents have authority over their children and that the law can support that authority persists today. For example, at least some States make it a crime to lure or entice a minor away from the minorâs parent. See, e.g., Cal. Penal Code Ann. §272(b)(1) (West 2008); Fla. Stat. §787.03 (2010). Every State in the Union still establishes a minimum age for marriage without parental or judicial consent. Cf. Roper v. Simmons, 543 U. S. 551, 558 (Ap pendix D to opinion of Court) (2005). Individuals less than 18 years old cannot enlist in the military without parental consent. 10 U. S. C. §505(a). And minors remain subject to curfew laws across the country, see Brief for Louisiana et al. as Amici Curiae 16, and cannot unilaterally consent to most medical procedures, id., at 15. Moreover, there are many things minors today cannot do at all, whether they have parental consent or not. State laws set minimum ages for voting and jury duty. See Roper, supra, at 581â585 (Appendixes B and C to opinion of Court). In California (the State at issue here), minors cannot drive for hire or drive a school bus, Cal. Veh. Code Ann. §§12515, 12516 (West 2010), purchase tobacco, Cal. Penal Code Ann. §308(b) (West 2008), play bingo for money, §326.5(e), or execute a will, Cal. Probate Code Ann. §6220 (West 2009). My understanding of âthe freedom of speechâ is also consistent with this Courtâs precedents. To be sure, the 18 BROWN v. ENTERTAINMENT MERCHANTS ASSN. THOMAS, J., dissenting Court has held that children are entitled to the protection of the First Amendment, see, e.g., Erznoznik v. Jackson ville, 422 U. S. 205, 212â213 (1975), and the government may not unilaterally dictate what children can say or hear, see id., at 213â214; Tinker v. Des Moines Independ ent Community School Dist., 393 U. S. 503, 511 (1969). But this Court has never held, until today, that âthe free dom of speechâ includes a right to speak to minors (or a right of minors to access speech) without going through the minorsâ parents. To the contrary, â[i]t is well settled that a State or municipality can adopt more stringent controls on communicative materials available to youths than on those available to adults.â Erznoznik, supra, at 212; cf. post, at 3 (BREYER, J., dissenting). The Courtâs constitutional jurisprudence âhistorically has reflected Western civilization concepts of the family as a unit with broad parental authority over minor children.â Parham v. J. R., 442 U. S. 584, 602 (1979). Under that case law, âlegislature[s] [can] properly conclude that par ents and others, teachers for example, who have . . . pri mary responsibility for childrenâs well-being are entitled to the support of laws designed to aid discharge of that re sponsibility.â Ginsberg v. New York, 390 U. S. 629, 639 (1968); see also Bellotti v. Baird, 443 U. S. 622, 635 (1979) (opinion of Powell, J.) (â[T]he State is entitled to adjust its legal system to account for childrenâs vulnerability and their needs for concern, . . . sympathy, and . . . paternal attentionâ (internal quotation marks omitted)). This is because âthe tradition of parental authority is not incon sistent with our tradition of individual liberty; rather, the former is one of the basic presuppositions of the latter.â Id., at 638; id., at 638â639 (âLegal restrictions on minors, especially those supportive of the parental role, may be important to the childâs chances for the full growth and maturity that make eventual participation in a free soci ety meaningful and rewardingâ). Cite as: 564 U. S. ____ (2011) 19 THOMAS, J., dissenting III The California law at issue here prohibits the sale or rental of âviolent video game[s]â to minors, defined as anyone âunder 18 years of age.â Cal. Civ. Code Ann. §§1746.1(a), 1746 (West 2009). A violation of the law is punishable by a civil fine of up to $1,000. §1746.3. Criti cally, the law does not prohibit adults from buying or renting violent video games for a minor or prohibit minors from playing such games. Cf. ante, at 10 (ALITO, J., con curring in judgment); post, at 10 (BREYER, J., dissenting). The law also does not restrict a âminorâs parent, grandpar ent, aunt, uncle, or legal guardianâ from selling or renting him a violent video game. §1746.1(c). Respondents, associations of companies in the video game industry, brought a preenforcement challenge to Californiaâs law, claiming that on its face the law violates the free speech rights of their members. The Court holds that video games are speech for purposes of the First Amendment and finds the statute facially unconstitu tional. See ante, at 2â3, 11â17. I disagree. Under any of this Courtâs standards for a facial First Amendment challenge, this one must fail. The video game associations cannot show âthat no set of circumstances exists under which [the law] would be valid,â âthat the statute lacks any plainly legitimate sweep,â or that âa substantial number of its applications are unconstitu tional, judged in relation to the statuteâs plainly legitimate sweep.â Stevens, 559 U. S., at ___ (slip op., at 10) (internal quotation marks omitted). Even assuming that video games are speech, in most applications the California law does not implicate the First Amendment. All that the law does is prohibit the direct sale or rental of a violent video game to a minor by someone other than the minorâs par ent, grandparent, aunt, uncle, or legal guardian. Where a minor has a parent or guardian, as is usually true, the law does not prevent that minor from obtaining a violent video 20 BROWN v. ENTERTAINMENT MERCHANTS ASSN. THOMAS, J., dissenting game with his parentâs or guardianâs help. In the typical case, the only speech affected is speech that bypasses a minorâs parent or guardian. Because such speech does not fall within âthe freedom of speechâ as originally under stood, Californiaâs law does not ordinarily implicate the First Amendment and is not facially unconstitutional.3 * * * âThe freedom of speech,â as originally understood, does not include a right to speak to minors without going through the minorsâ parents or guardians. Therefore, I cannot agree that the statute at issue is facially unconsti tutional under the First Amendment. I respectfully dissent. ââââââ 3 Whether the statute would survive an as-applied challenge in the unusual case of an emancipated minor is a question for another day. To decide this case, it is enough that the statute is not unconstitutional on its face. Cite as: 564 U. S. ____ (2011) 1 BREYER, J., dissenting SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES _________________ No. 08â1448 _________________ EDMUND G. BROWN, JR., GOVERNOR OF CAL- IFORNIA, ET AL., PETITIONERS v. ENTERTAIN- MENT MERCHANTS ASSOCIATION ET AL. ON WRIT OF CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE NINTH CIRCUIT [June 27, 2011] JUSTICE BREYER, dissenting. California imposes a civil fine of up to $1,000 upon any person who distributes a violent video game in California without labeling it â18,â or who sells or rents a labeled violent video game to a person under the age of 18. Rep- resentatives of the video game and software industries, claiming that the statute violates the First Amendment on its face, seek an injunction against its enforcement. Ap plying traditional First Amendment analysis, I would uphold the statute as constitutional on its face and would consequently reject the industriesâ facial challenge. I A Californiaâs statute defines a violent video game as: A game in which a player âkill[s], maim[s], dismember[s], or sexually assault[s] an image of a human being,â and â[a] reasonable person, considering the game as a whole, would find [the game] appeals to a deviant or morbid interest of minors,â and â[the game] is patently offensive to prevailing standards in the community as to what is suitable for minors,â 2 BROWN v. ENTERTAINMENT MERCHANTS ASSN. BREYER, J., dissenting and âthe game, as a whole, . . . lack[s] serious literary, ar tistic, political, or scientific value for minors.â Cal. Civ. Code Ann. §1746(d)(1) (West 2009). The statute in effect forbids the sale of such a game to minors unless they are accompanied by a parent; it re quires the makers of the game to affix a label identifying it as a game suitable only for those aged 18 and over; it exempts retailers from liability unless such a label is properly affixed to the game; and it imposes a civil fine of up to $1,000 upon a violator. See §§1746.1â1746.3. B A facial challenge to this statute based on the First Amendment can succeed only if âa substantial number of its applications are unconstitutional, judged in relation to the statuteâs plainly legitimate sweep.â United States v. Stevens, 559 U. S. __, __ (2010) (slip op., at 10) (internal quotation marks omitted). Moreover, it is more difficult to mount a facial First Amendment attack on a statute that seeks to regulate activity that involves action as well as speech. See Broadrick v. Oklahoma, 413 U. S. 601, 614â 615 (1973). Hence, I shall focus here upon an area within which I believe the State can legitimately apply its stat ute, namely sales to minors under the age of 17 (the age cutoff used by the industryâs own ratings system), of highly realistic violent video games, which a reasonable game maker would know meet the Actâs criteria. That area lies at the heart of the statute. I shall assume that the number of instances in which the State will enforce the statute within that area is comparatively large, and that the number outside that area (for example, sales to 17-year-olds) is comparatively small. And the activity the statute regulates combines speech with action (a virtual form of target practice). Cite as: 564 U. S. ____ (2011) 3 BREYER, J., dissenting C In determining whether the statute is unconstitutional, I would apply both this Courtâs âvaguenessâ precedents and a strict form of First Amendment scrutiny. In doing so, the special First Amendment category I find relevant is not (as the Court claims) the category of âdepictions of violence,â ante, at 8, but rather the category of âprotection of children.â This Court has held that the âpower of the state to control the conduct of children reaches beyond the scope of its authority over adults.â Prince v. Massachu setts, 321 U. S. 158, 170 (1944). And the â âregulatio[n] of communication addressed to [children] need not conform to the requirements of the [F]irst [A]mendment in the same way as those applicable to adults.â â Ginsberg v. New York, 390 U. S. 629, 638, n. 6 (1968) (quoting Emerson, Toward a General Theory of the First Amendment, 72 Yale L. J. 877, 939 (1963)). The majorityâs claim that the California statute, if up held, would create a ânew categor[y] of unprotected speech,â ante, at 3, 6, is overstated. No one here argues that depictions of violence, even extreme violence, auto matically fall outside the First Amendmentâs protective scope as, for example, do obscenity and depictions of child pornography. We properly speak of categories of expres sion that lack protection when, like âchild pornography,â the category is broad, when it applies automatically, and when the State can prohibit everyone, including adults, from obtaining access to the material within it. But where, as here, careful analysis must precede a narrower judicial conclusion (say, denying protection to a shout of âfireâ in a crowded theater, or to an effort to teach a terror ist group how to peacefully petition the United Nations), we do not normally describe the result as creating a ânew category of unprotected speech.â See Schenck v. United States, 249 U. S. 47, 52 (1919); Holder v. Humanitarian Law Project, 561 U. S. __ (2010). 4 BROWN v. ENTERTAINMENT MERCHANTS ASSN. BREYER, J., dissenting Thus, in Stevens, after rejecting the claim that all de pictions of animal cruelty (a category) fall outside the First Amendmentâs protective scope, we went on to decide whether the particular statute at issue violates the First Amendment under traditional standards; and we held that, because the statute was overly broad, it was invalid. Similarly, here the issue is whether, applying traditional First Amendment standards, this statute does, or does not, pass muster. II In my view, Californiaâs statute provides âfair notice of what is prohibited,â and consequently it is not impermis sibly vague. United States v. Williams, 553 U. S. 285, 304 (2008). Ginsberg explains why that is so. The Court there considered a New York law that forbade the sale to minors of a âpicture, photograph, drawing, sculpture, motion pic ture film, or similar visual representation or image of a person or portion of the human body which depicts nudity . . . ,â that âpredominately appeals to the prurient, shameful or morbid interest of minors,â and âis patently offensive to prevailing standards in the adult community as a whole with respect to what is suitable material for minors,â and âis utterly without redeeming social importance for minors.â 390 U. S., at 646â647. This Court upheld the New York statute in Ginsberg (which is sometimes unfortunately confused with a very Cite as: 564 U. S. ____ (2011) 5 BREYER, J., dissenting different, earlier case, Ginzburg v. United States, 383 U. S. 463 (1966)). The five-Justice majority, in an opinion writ ten by Justice Brennan, wrote that the statute was suf- ficiently clear. 390 U. S., at 643â645. No Member of the Court voiced any vagueness objection. See id., at 648â650 (Stewart, J., concurring in result); id., at 650â671 (Doug las, J., joined by Black, J., dissenting); id., at 671â675 (Fortas, J., dissenting). Comparing the language of Californiaâs statute (set forth supra, at 1â2) with the language of New Yorkâs statute (set forth immediately above), it is difficult to find any vagueness-related difference. Why are the words âkill,â âmaim,â and âdismemberâ any more difficult to understand than the word ânudity?â JUSTICE ALITO ob jects that these words do ânot perform the narrowing functionâ that this Court has required in adult obscenity cases, where statutes can only cover â âhard coreâ â depic tions. Ante, at 6 (opinion concurring in judgment). But the relevant comparison is not to adult obscenity cases but to Ginsberg, which dealt with ânudity,â a category no more ânarrowâ than killing and maiming. And in any event, narrowness and vagueness do not necessarily have any thing to do with one another. All that is required for vagueness purposes is that the terms âkill,â âmaim,â and âdismemberâ give fair notice as to what they cover, which they do. The remainder of Californiaâs definition copies, almost word for word, the language this Court used in Miller v. California, 413 U. S. 15 (1973), in permitting a total ban on material that satisfied its definition (one enforced with criminal penalties). The California lawâs reliance on âcommunity standardsâ adheres to Miller, and in Fort Wayne Books, Inc. v. Indiana, 489 U. S. 46, 57â58 (1989), this Court specifically upheld the use of Millerâs language against charges of vagueness. California only departed from the Miller formulation in two significant respects: It 6 BROWN v. ENTERTAINMENT MERCHANTS ASSN. BREYER, J., dissenting substituted the word âdeviantâ for the words âprurientâ and âshameful,â and it three times added the words âfor minors.â The word âdeviantâ differs from âprurientâ and âshameful,â but it would seem no less suited to defining and narrowing the reach of the statute. And the addition of âfor minorsâ to a version of the Miller standard was approved in Ginsberg, 390 U. S., at 643, even though the New York law âdr[ew] no distinction between young chil dren and adolescents who are nearing the age of majority,â ante, at 8 (opinion of ALITO, J.). Both the Miller standard and the law upheld in Gins berg lack perfect clarity. But that fact reflects the dif ficulty of the Courtâs long search for words capable of protecting expression without depriving the State of a legitimate constitutional power to regulate. As is well known, at one point Justice Stewart thought he could do no better in defining obscenity than, âI know it when I see it.â Jacobellis v. Ohio, 378 U. S. 184, 197 (1964) (concur ring opinion). And Justice Douglas dissented from Millerâs standard, which he thought was still too vague. 413 U. S., at 39â40. Ultimately, however, this Court accepted the âcommunity standardsâ tests used in Miller and Ginsberg. They reflect the fact that sometimes, even when a precise standard proves elusive, it is easy enough to identify instances that fall within a legitimate regulation. And they seek to draw a line, which, while favoring free ex pression, will nonetheless permit a legislature to find the words necessary to accomplish a legitimate constitutional objective. Cf. Williams, supra, at 304 (the Constitution does not always require â âperfect clarity and precise guid ance,â â even when â âexpressive activityâ â is involved). What, then, is the difference between Ginsberg and Miller on the one hand and the California law on the other? It will often be easy to pick out cases at which Californiaâs statute directly aims, involving, say, a charac ter who shoots out a police officerâs knee, douses him with Cite as: 564 U. S. ____ (2011) 7 BREYER, J., dissenting gasoline, lights him on fire, urinates on his burning body, and finally kills him with a gunshot to the head. (Foot- age of one such game sequence has been submitted in the record.) See also ante, at 14â15 (ALITO, J., concurring in judgment). As in Miller and Ginsberg, the California law clearly protects even the most violent games that possess serious literary, artistic, political, or scientific value. §1746(d)(1)(A)(iii). And it is easier here than in Miller or Ginsberg to separate the sheep from the goats at the statuteâs border. That is because here the industry it- self has promulgated standards and created a review process, in which adults who âtypically have experience with childrenâ assess what games are inappropriate for minors. See Entertainment Software Rating Board, Rating Process, online at http://www.esrb.org/ratings/&ratings_ process.jsp (all Internet materials as visited June 24, 2011, and available in Clerk of Courtâs case file). There is, of course, one obvious difference: The Ginsberg statute concerned depictions of ânudity,â while Californiaâs statute concerns extremely violent video games. But for purposes of vagueness, why should that matter? JUSTICE ALITO argues that the Miller standard sufficed because there are âcertain generally accepted norms concerning expression related to sex,â whereas there are no similarly âaccepted standards regarding the suitability of violent entertainment.â Ante, at 7â8. But there is no evidence that is so. The Court relied on âcommunity standardsâ in Miller precisely because of the difficulty of articulating âaccepted normsâ about depictions of sex. I can find no differenceâhistorical or otherwiseâthat is relevant to the vagueness question. Indeed, the majorityâs examples of literary descriptions of violence, on which JUSTICE ALITO relies, do not show anything relevant at all. After all, one can find in literature as many (if not more) descriptions of physical love as descriptions of violence. Indeed, sex âhas been a theme in art and literature 8 BROWN v. ENTERTAINMENT MERCHANTS ASSN. BREYER, J., dissenting throughout the ages.â Ashcroft v. Free Speech Coalition, 535 U. S. 234, 246 (2002). For every Homer, there is a Titian. For every Dante, there is an Ovid. And for all the teenagers who have read the original versions of Grimmâs Fairy Tales, I suspect there are those who know the story of Lady Godiva. Thus, I can find no meaningful vagueness-related dif ferences between Californiaâs law and the New York law upheld in Ginsberg. And if there remain any vagueness problems, the state courts can cure them through inter pretation. See Erznoznik v. Jacksonville, 422 U. S. 205, 216 (1975) (â[S]tate statute should not be deemed facially invalid unless it is not readily subject to a narrowing construction by the state courtsâ). Cf. Ginsberg, supra, at 644 (relying on the fact that New York Court of Appeals would read a knowledge requirement into the statute); Berry v. Santa Barbara,
, 1088â 1089,
, 669 (1995) (reading a knowl edge requirement into a statute). Consequently, for pur poses of this facial challenge, I would not find the statute unconstitutionally vague. III Video games combine physical action with expression. Were physical activity to predominate in a game, govern ment could appropriately intervene, say by requiring parents to accompany children when playing a game in volving actual target practice, or restricting the sale of toys presenting physical dangers to children. See gener ally Consumer Product Safety Improvement Act of 2008, 122 Stat. 3016 (âTitle IâChildrenâs Product Safetyâ). But because video games also embody important expressive and artistic elements, I agree with the Court that the First Amendment significantly limits the Stateâs power to regu late. And I would determine whether the State has ex ceeded those limits by applying a strict standard of review. Cite as: 564 U. S. ____ (2011) 9 BREYER, J., dissenting Like the majority, I believe that the California law must be ânarrowly tailoredâ to further a âcompelling interest,â without there being a âless restrictiveâ alternative that would be âat least as effective.â Reno v. American Civil Liberties Union, 521 U. S. 844, 874, 875, 879 (1997). I would not apply this strict standard âmechanically.â United States v. Playboy Entertainment Group, Inc., 529 U. S. 803, 841 (2000) (BREYER, J., joined by Rehnquist, C. J., and OâConnor and SCALIA, JJ., dissenting). Rather, in applying it, I would evaluate the degree to which the statute injures speech-related interests, the nature of the potentially-justifying âcompelling interests,â the degree to which the statute furthers that interest, the nature and effectiveness of possible alternatives, and, in light of this evaluation, whether, overall, âthe statute works speech related harm . . . out of proportion to the benefits that the statute seeks to provide.â Ibid. See also Burson v. Free man, 504 U. S. 191, 210 (1992) (plurality opinion) (apply ing strict scrutiny and finding relevant the lack of a âsignificant impingementâ on speech). First Amendment standards applied in this way are difficult but not impossible to satisfy. Applying âstrict scrutinyâ the Court has upheld restrictions on speech that, for example, ban the teaching of peaceful dispute resolu tion to a group on the State Departmentâs list of terrorist organizations, Holder, 561 U. S., at ___ (slip op., at 22â34); but cf. id., at ___ (slip op., at 1 ) (BREYER, J., dissenting), and limit speech near polling places, Burson, supra, at 210â211 (plurality opinion). And applying less clearly defined but still rigorous standards, the Court has allowed States to require disclosure of petition signers, Doe v. Reed, 561 U. S. ___ (2010), and to impose campaign con tribution limits that were â âclosely drawnâ to match a âsufficiently important interest,â â Nixon v. Shrink Missouri Government PAC, 528 U. S. 377, 387â388 (2000). Moreover, although the Court did not specify the âlevel 10 BROWN v. ENTERTAINMENT MERCHANTS ASSN. BREYER, J., dissenting of scrutinyâ it applied in Ginsberg, we have subsequently described that case as finding a âcompelling interestâ in protecting children from harm sufficient to justify limita tions on speech. See Sable Communications of Cal., Inc. v. FCC, 492 U. S. 115, 126 (1989). Since the Court in Gins berg specified that the statuteâs prohibition applied to material that was not obscene, 390 U. S., at 634, I cannot dismiss Ginsberg on the ground that it concerned obscen ity. But cf. ante, at 6 (majority opinion). Nor need I de pend upon the fact that the Court in Ginsberg insisted only that the legislature have a ârationalâ basis for finding the depictions there at issue harmful to children. 390 U. S., at 639. For in this case, California has substan tiated its claim of harm with considerably stronger evidence. A Californiaâs law imposes no more than a modest restric tion on expression. The statute prevents no one from playing a video game, it prevents no adult from buying a video game, and it prevents no child or adolescent from obtaining a game provided a parent is willing to help. §1746.1(c). All it prevents is a child or adolescent from buying, without a parentâs assistance, a gruesomely vio lent video game of a kind that the industry itself tells us it wants to keep out of the hands of those under the age of 17. See Brief for Respondents 8. Nor is the statute, if upheld, likely to create a prece- dent that would adversely affect other media, say films, or videos, or books. A typical video game involves a signifi cant amount of physical activity. See ante, at 13â14 (ALITO, J., concurring in judgment) (citing examples of the increasing interactivity of video game controllers). And pushing buttons that achieve an interactive, virtual form of target practice (using images of human beings as tar gets), while containing an expressive component, is not Cite as: 564 U. S. ____ (2011) 11 BREYER, J., dissenting just like watching a typical movie. See infra, at 14. B The interest that California advances in support of the statute is compelling. As this Court has previously de scribed that interest, it consists of both (1) the âbasicâ parental claim âto authority in their own household to direct the rearing of their children,â which makes it proper to enact âlaws designed to aid discharge of [parental] responsibility,â and (2) the Stateâs âindependent interest in the well-being of its youth.â Ginsberg, 390 U. S., at 639â 640. Cf. id., at 639, n. 7 (â â[O]ne can well distinguish laws which do not impose a morality on children, but which support the right of parents to deal with the morals of their children as they see fitâ â (quoting Henkin, Morals and the Constitution: The Sin of Obscenity, 63 Colum. L. Rev. 391, 413, n. 68 (1963))). And where these interests work in tandem, it is not fatally âunderinclusiveâ for a State to advance its interests in protecting children against the special harms present in an interactive video game medium through a default rule that still allows parents to provide their children with what their parents wish. Both interests are present here. As to the need to help parents guide their children, the Court noted in 1968 that â âparental control or guidance cannot always be provided.â â 390 U. S., at 640. Today, 5.3 million grade school-age children of working parents are routinely home alone. See Dept. of Commerce, Census Bureau, Whoâs Minding the Kids? Child Care Arrangements: Spring 2005/Summer 2006, p. 12 (2010), online at http:// www.census.gov/prod/2010pubs/p70-121.pdf. Thus, it has, if anything, become more important to supplement par entsâ authority to guide their childrenâs development. As to the Stateâs independent interest, we have pointed out that juveniles are more likely to show a â âlack of ma 12 BROWN v. ENTERTAINMENT MERCHANTS ASSN. BREYER, J., dissenting turityâ â and are âmore vulnerable or susceptible to nega tive influences and outside pressures,â and that their âcharacter . . . is not as well formed as that of an adult.â Roper v. Simmons, 543 U. S. 551, 569â570 (2005). And we have therefore recognized âa compelling interest in pro tecting the physical and psychological well-being of mi nors.â Sable Communications, supra, at 126. At the same time, there is considerable evidence that Californiaâs statute significantly furthers this compelling interest. That is, in part, because video games are excel lent teaching tools. Learning a practical task often means developing habits, becoming accustomed to performing the task, and receiving positive reinforcement when perform ing that task well. Video games can help develop habits, accustom the player to performance of the task, and reward the player for performing that task well. Why else would the Armed Forces incorporate video games into its training? See CNN, War Games: Military Train ing Goes High-Tech (Nov. 22, 2001), online at http://articles.cnn.com/2001â11â2 / tech / war.games_1_ict- 2 bill-swartout-real-world-training?_s=PM:TECH. When the military uses video games to help soldiers train for missions, it is using this medium for a beneficial purpose. But California argues that when the teaching features of video games are put to less desirable ends, harm can ensue. In particular, extremely violent games can harm children by rewarding them for being violently aggressive in play, and thereby often teaching them to be violently aggressive in life. And video games can cause more harm in this respect than can typically passive media, such as books or films or television programs. There are many scientific studies that support Califor niaâs views. Social scientists, for example, have found causal evidence that playing these games results in harm. Longitudinal studies, which measure changes over time, have found that increased exposure to violent video games Cite as: 564 U. S. ____ (2011) 13 BREYER, J., dissenting causes an increase in aggression over the same period. See Möller & KrahĂ©, Exposure to Violent Video Games and Aggression in German Adolescents: A Longitudinal Analysis, 35 Aggressive Behavior 75 (2009); Gentile & Gentile, Violent Video Games as Exemplary Teachers: A Conceptual Analysis, 37 J. Youth & Adolescence 127 (2008); Anderson et al., Longitudinal Effects of Violent Video Games on Aggression in Japan and the United States, 122 Pediatrics e1067 (2008); Wallenius & Puna mĂ€ki, Digital Game Violence and Direct Aggression in Adolescence: A Longitudinal Study of the Roles of Sex, Age, and Parent-Child Communication, 29 J. Applied Developmental Psychology 286 (2008). Experimental studies in laboratories have found that subjects randomly assigned to play a violent video game subsequently displayed more characteristics of aggression than those who played nonviolent games. See, e.g., Ander son et al., Violent Video Games: Specific Effects of Violent Content on Aggressive Thoughts and Behavior, 36 Ad vances in Experimental Soc. Psychology 199 (2004). Surveys of 8th and 9th grade students have found a correlation between playing violent video games and aggression. See, e.g., Gentile, Lynch, Linder, & Walsh, The Effects of Violent Video Game Habits On Adolescent Hostility, Aggressive Behaviors, and School Performance, 27 J. Adolescence 5 (2004). Cutting-edge neuroscience has shown that âvirtual violence in video game playing results in those neural patterns that are considered characteristic for aggressive cognition and behavior.â Weber, Ritterfeld, & Mathiak, Does Playing Violent Video Games Induce Aggression? Empirical Evidence of a Functional Magnetic Resonance Imaging Study, 8 Media Psychology 39, 51 (2006). And âmeta-analyses,â i.e., studies of all the studies, have concluded that exposure to violent video games âwas posi tively associated with aggressive behavior, aggressive 14 BROWN v. ENTERTAINMENT MERCHANTS ASSN. BREYER, J., dissenting cognition, and aggressive affect,â and that âplaying violent video games is a causal risk factor for long-term harmful outcomes.â Anderson et al., Violent Video Game Effects on Aggression, Empathy, and Prosocial Behavior in Eastern and Western Countries: A Meta-Analytic Review, 136 Psychological Bulletin 151, 167, 169 (2010) (emphasis added). Some of these studies take care to explain in a common- sense way why video games are potentially more harmful than, say, films or books or television. In essence, they say that the closer a childâs behavior comes, not to watch ing, but to acting out horrific violence, the greater the potential psychological harm. See Bushman & Hues mann, Aggression, in 2 Handbook of Social Pscyhology 833, 851 (S. Fiske, D. Gilbert, & G. Lindzey eds., 5th ed. 2010) (video games stimulate more aggression because â[p]eople learn better when they are actively involved,â players are âmore likely to identify with violent charac ters,â and âviolent games directly reward violent behav iorâ); Polman, de Castro, & van Aken, Experimental Study of the Differential Effects of Playing Versus Watching Violent Video Games on Childrenâs Aggressive Behavior, 34 Aggressive Behavior 256 (2008) (finding greater ag gression resulting from playing, as opposed to watching, a violent game); C. Anderson, D. Gentile, & K. Buckley, Violent Video Game Effects on Children and Adolescents 136â137 (2007) (three studies finding greater effects from games as opposed to television). See also infra, at 15â16 (statements of expert public health associations agreeing that interactive games can be more harmful than âpassiveâ media like television); ante, at 12â17 (ALITO, J., concur ring in judgment). Experts debate the conclusions of all these studies. Like many, perhaps most, studies of human behavior, each study has its critics, and some of those critics have pro duced studies of their own in which they reach different Cite as: 564 U. S. ____ (2011) 15 BREYER, J., dissenting conclusions. (I list both sets of research in the appen dixes.) I, like most judges, lack the social science expertise to say definitively who is right. But associations of public health professionals who do possess that expertise have reviewed many of these studies and found a significant risk that violent video games, when compared with more passive media, are particularly likely to cause children harm. Eleven years ago, for example, the American Academy of Pediatrics, the American Academy of Child & Adoles cent Psychiatry, the American Psychological Association, the American Medical Association, the American Academy of Family Physicians, and the American Psychiatric Asso ciation released a joint statement, which said: â[O]ver 1000 studies . . . point overwhelmingly to a causal connection between media violence and aggres sive behavior in some children . . . [and, though less research had been done at that time, preliminary studies indicated that] the impact of violent interac tive entertainment (video games and other interactive media) on young people . . . may be significantly more severe than that wrought by television, movies, or mu sic.â Joint Statement on the Impact of Entertainment Violence on Children (2000) (emphasis added), online at http://www.aap.org/advocacy/releases/jstmtevc.htm. Five years later, after more research had been done, the American Psychological Association adopted a resolution that said: â[C]omprehensive analysis of violent interactive video game research suggests such exposure . . . increases aggressive behavior, . . . increases aggres sive thoughts, . . . increases angry feelings, . . . de creases helpful behavior, and . . . increases physio- logical arousal.â Resolution on Violence in Video Games and Interactive Media (2005), online at 16 BROWN v. ENTERTAINMENT MERCHANTS ASSN. BREYER, J., dissenting http:// www.apa.org / about / governance / council / policy/ interactive-media.pdf. The Association added: â[T]he practice, repetition, and rewards for acts of vio lence may be more conducive to increasing aggressive behavior among children and youth than passively watching violence on TV and in films.â Ibid. (empha sis added). Four years after that, in 2009, the American Academy of Pediatrics issued a statement in significant part about interactive media. It said: âStudies of these rapidly growing and ever-more sophisticated types of media have indicated that the effects of child-initiated virtual violence may be even more profound than those of passive media such as television. In many games the child or teenager is âembeddedâ in the game and uses a âjoystickâ (handheld controller) that enhances both the experience and the aggressive feelings.â Policy StatementâMedia Vio lence, 124 Pediatrics 1495, 1498 (2009) (emphasis added). It added: âCorrelational and experimental studies have re vealed that violent video games lead to increases in aggressive behavior and aggressive thinking and de creases in prosocial behavior. Recent longitudinal studies . . . have revealed that in as little as 3 months, high exposure to violent video games increased physi cal aggression. Other recent longitudinal studies . . . have revealed similar effects across 2 years.â Ibid. (footnotes omitted). Unlike the majority, I would find sufficient grounds in these studies and expert opinions for this Court to defer to Cite as: 564 U. S. ____ (2011) 17 BREYER, J., dissenting an elected legislatureâs conclusion that the video games in question are particularly likely to harm children. This Court has always thought it owed an elected legislature some degree of deference in respect to legislative facts of this kind, particularly when they involve technical mat ters that are beyond our competence, and even in First Amendment cases. See Holder, 561 U. S., at ___ (slip op., at 28â29) (deferring, while applying strict scrutiny, to the Governmentâs national security judgments); Turner Broadcasting System, Inc. v. FCC, 520 U. S. 180, 195â196 (1997) (deferring, while applying intermediate scrutiny, to the Governmentâs technological judgments). The majority, in reaching its own, opposite conclusion about the validity of the relevant studies, grants the legislature no deference at all. Compare ante, at 12â13 (stating that the studies do not provide evidence that violent video games âcauseâ harm (emphasis deleted)), with supra, at 12â13 (citing longitudinal studies finding causation). C I can find no âless restrictiveâ alternative to Californiaâs law that would be âat least as effective.â See Reno, 521 U. S., at 874. The majority points to a voluntary alterna tive: The industry tries to prevent those under 17 from buying extremely violent games by labeling those games with an âMâ (Mature) and encouraging retailers to restrict their sales to those 17 and older. See ante, at 15â16. But this voluntary system has serious enforcement gaps. When California enacted its law, a Federal Trade Com mission (FTC) study had found that nearly 70% of unac companied 13- to 16-year-olds were able to buy M-rated video games. FTC, Marketing Violent Entertainment to Children 27 (2004), online at http://www.ftc.gov/os/2004/ 07/040708kidsviolencerpt.pdf. Subsequently the volun- tary program has become more effective. But as of the FTCâs most recent update to Congress, 20% of those 18 BROWN v. ENTERTAINMENT MERCHANTS ASSN. BREYER, J., dissenting under 17 are still able to buy M-rated video games, and, breaking down sales by store, one finds that this num- ber rises to nearly 50% in the case of one large national chain. FTC, Marketing Violent Entertainment to Chil- dren 28 (2009), online at http://www.ftc.gov/os/2009/12/ P994511violententertainment.pdf. And the industry could easily revert back to the substantial noncompliance that existed in 2004, particularly after todayâs broad ruling reduces the industryâs incentive to police itself. The industry also argues for an alternative technological solution, namely âfiltering at the console level.â Brief for Respondents 53. But it takes only a quick search of the Internet to find guides explaining how to circum vent any such technological controls. YouTube viewers, for example, have watched one of those guides (called âHow to bypass parental controls on the Xbox 360â) more than 47,000 times. See http://www.youtube.com/watch?v= CFlVfVmvN6k. IV The upshot is that Californiaâs statute, as applied to its heartland of applications (i.e., buyers under 17; extremely violent, realistic video games), imposes a restriction on speech that is modest at most. That restriction is justified by a compelling interest (supplementing parentsâ efforts to prevent their children from purchasing potentially harm ful violent, interactive material). And there is no equally effective, less restrictive alternative. Californiaâs statute is consequently constitutional on its faceâthough litigants remain free to challenge the statute as applied in particu lar instances, including any effort by the State to apply it to minors aged 17. I add that the majorityâs different conclusion creates a serious anomaly in First Amendment law. Ginsberg makes clear that a State can prohibit the sale to minors of depictions of nudity; today the Court makes clear that a Cite as: 564 U. S. ____ (2011) 19 BREYER, J., dissenting State cannot prohibit the sale to minors of the most vio lent interactive video games. But what sense does it make to forbid selling to a 13-year-old boy a magazine with an image of a nude woman, while protecting a sale to that 13 year-old of an interactive video game in which he actively, but virtually, binds and gags the woman, then tortures and kills her? What kind of First Amendment would permit the government to protect children by restrict- ing sales of that extremely violent video game only when the womanâbound, gagged, tortured, and killedâis also topless? This anomaly is not compelled by the First Amendment. It disappears once one recognizes that extreme violence, where interactive, and without literary, artistic, or similar justification, can prove at least as, if not more, harmful to children as photographs of nudity. And the record here is more than adequate to support such a view. That is why I believe that Ginsberg controls the outcome here a fortiori. And it is why I believe Californiaâs law is constitutional on its face. This case is ultimately less about censorship than it is about education. Our Constitution cannot succeed in securing the liberties it seeks to protect unless we can raise future generations committed cooperatively to mak ing our system of government work. Education, however, is about choices. Sometimes, children need to learn by making choices for themselves. Other times, choices are made for childrenâby their parents, by their teachers, and by the people acting democratically through their governments. In my view, the First Amendment does not disable government from helping parents make such a choice hereâa choice not to have their children buy ex tremely violent, interactive video games, which they more than reasonably fear pose only the risk of harm to those children. For these reasons, I respectfully dissent. 20 BROWN v. ENTERTAINMENT MERCHANTS ASSN. BREYER, J., dissenting Appendix A to the opinion of BREYER, J. APPENDIXES With the assistance of the Supreme Court Library, I have compiled these two appendixes listing peer-reviewed academic journal articles on the topic of psychological harm resulting from playing violent video games. The library conducted a search for relevant articles on the following databases: PsycINFO, PubMed, Academic Search Premier, ArticleFirst (OCLC), and Dialog (files 1, 7, 34, 98, 121, 142, 144, 149). The following search terms were used: â(video* or computer or arcade or online) and (game*) and (attack* or fight* or aggress* or violen* or hostil* or ang* or arous* or prosocial or help* or desens* or empathy).â After eliminating irrelevant matches based on title or abstract, I categorized these articles as either supporting the hypothesis that violent video games are harmful (listed in Appendix A), or not supporting/rejecting the hypothesis that violent video games are harmful (listed in Appendix B). Many, but not all, of these articles were available to the California Legislature or the parties in briefing this case. I list them because they suggest that there is substantial (though controverted) evidence supporting the expert associations of public health professionals that have con cluded that violent video games can cause children psycho logical harm. See supra, at 15â16. And consequently, these studies help to substantiate the validity of the origi nal judgment of the California Legislature, as well as that judgmentâs continuing validity. A Anderson & Bushman, Effects of Violent Video Games on Aggressive Behavior, Aggressive Cognition, Aggressive Affect, Physiological Arousal, and Prosocial Behavior: A Meta-Analytic Review of the Scientific Literature, 12 Psychological Science: J. Am. Psychological Society 353 Cite as: 564 U. S. ____ (2011) 21 BREYER, J., dissenting Appendix A to the opinion of BREYER, J. (2001). Anderson & Dill, Video Games and Aggressive Thoughts, Feelings, & Behavior in the Laboratory and in Life, 78 J. Personality & Soc. Psychology 772 (2000). Anderson et al., Violent Video Games: Specific Effects of Violent Content on Aggressive Thoughts and Behavior, 36 Advances in Experimental Soc. Psychology 199 (2004). Anderson & Ford, Affect of the Game Player: Short-Term Effects of Highly and Mildly Aggressive Video Games, 12 Personality & Soc. Psychology Bull. 390 (1986). Anderson & Morrow, Competitive Aggression Without Interaction: Effects of Competitive Versus Cooperative Instructions on Aggressive Behavior in Video Games, 21 Personality & Soc. Psychology Bull. 1020 (1995). Anderson et al., Longitudinal Effects of Violent Video Games on Aggression in Japan and the United States, 122 Pediatrics e1067 (2008). Anderson et al., Violent Video Game Effects on Aggres sion, Empathy, and Prosocial Behavior in Eastern and Western Countries: A Meta-Analytic Review, 136 Psy chological Bull. 151 (2010). Anderson, An Update on the Effects of Playing Violent Video Games, 27 J. Adolescence 113 (2004). Anderson et al., The Influence of Media Violence on Youth, 4 Psychological Science in the Public Interest 81 (2003). Anderson & Carnagey, Causal Effects of Violent Sports Video Games on Aggression: Is it Competitiveness or Violent Content? 45 J. Experimental Soc. Psychology 731 (2009). Anderson & Murphy, Violent Video Games and Aggressive Behavior in Young Women, 29 Aggressive Behavior 423 (2003). Arriaga, Esteves, Carneiro, & Monteiro, Violent Computer Games and Their Effects on State Hostility and Physio logical Arousal, 32 Aggressive Behavior 358 (2006). 22 BROWN v. ENTERTAINMENT MERCHANTS ASSN. BREYER, J., dissenting Appendix A to the opinion of BREYER, J. Arriaga, Esteves, Carneiro, & Monteiro, Are the Effects of Unreal Violent Video Games Pronounced When Playing With a Virtual Reality System? 34 Aggressive Behavior 521 (2008). Baldaro et al., Aggressive and Non-Violent Videogames: Short-Term Psychological and Cardiovascular Effects on Habitual Players, 20 Stress & Health: J. Intâl Society for Investigation of Stress 203 (2004). Ballard, Hamby, Panee, & Nivens, Repeated Exposure to Video Game Play Results in Decreased Blood Pressure Responding, 8 Media Psychology 323 (2006). Ballard & Lineberger, Video Game Violence and Confed erate Gender: Effects on Reward and Punishment Given by College Males, 41 Sex Roles 541 (1999). Ballard & Wiest, Mortal Kombat (tm): The Effects of Violent Videogame Play on Malesâ Hostility and Cardio vascular Responding, 26 J. Applied Soc. Psychology 717 (1996). Barlett, Branch, Rodeheffer, & Harris, How Long do the Short-Term Violent Video Game Effects Last? 35 Ag gressive Behavior 225 (2009). Barlett, Rodeheffer, Baldassaro, Hinkin, & Harris, The Effect of Advances in Video Game Technology and Con tent on Aggressive Cognitions, Hostility, and Heart Rate, 11 Media Psychology 540 (2008). Barlett, Harris, & Baldassaro, Longer You Play, the More Hostile You Feel: Examination of First Person Shooter Video Games and Aggression During Video Game Play, 33 Aggressive Behavior 486 (2007). Barlett, Harris, & Bruey, The Effect of the Amount of Blood in a Violent Video Game on Aggression, Hostility, and Arousal, 44 J. Experimental Soc. Psychology 539 (2008). Barlett & Rodeheffer, Effects of Realism on Extended Violent and Nonviolent Video Game Play on Aggressive Thoughts, Feelings, and Physiological Arousal, 35 Ag Cite as: 564 U. S. ____ (2011) 23 BREYER, J., dissenting Appendix A to the opinion of BREYER, J. gressive Behavior 213 (2009). Barlett, Anderson, & Swing, Video Game Effectsâ Confirmed, Suspected, and Speculative: A Review of the Evidence, 40 Simulation & Gaming 377 (2009). Bartholow, Sestir, & Davis, Correlates and Consequences of Exposure to Video Game Violence: Hostile Personal ity, Empathy, and Aggressive Behavior, 31 Personality & Soc. Psychology Bull. 1573 (2005). Bartholow & Anderson, Effects of Violent Video Games on Aggressive Behavior: Potential Sex Differences, 38 J. Experimental Soc. Psychology 283 (2002). Bartholow, Bushman, & Sestir, Chronic Violent Video Game Exposure and Desensitization to Violence: Behav ioral and Event-Related Brain Potential Data, 42 J. Ex perimental Soc. Psychology 532 (2006). Bluemke, Friedrich, & Zumbach, The Influence of Violent and Nonviolent Computer Games on Implicit Measures of Aggressiveness, 36 Aggressive Behavior 1 (2010). Brady & Matthews, Effects of Media Violence on Health- Related Outcomes Among Young Men, 160 Archives of Pediatrics & Adolescent Med. 341 (2006). Browne & Hamilton-Giachritsis, The Influence of Violent Media on Children and Adolescents: A Public-Health Approach, 365 Lancet 702 (2005). Bushman & Anderson, Violent Video Games and Hostile Expectations: A Test of the General Aggression Model, 28 Personality & Soc. Psychology Bull. 1679 (2002). Bushman & Anderson, Comfortably Numb: Desensitizing Effects of Violent Media on Helping Others, 20 Psycho logical Science: J. Am. Psychological Society 273 (2009). Bushman, Rothstein, & Anderson, Much Ado About Some thing: Violent Video Game Effects and a School of Red Herring: Reply to Ferguson and Kilburn, 136 Psycho logical Bull. 182 (2010). Calvert & Tan, Impact of Virtual Reality on Young Adultsâ Physiological Arousal and Aggressive Thoughts: Interac 24 BROWN v. ENTERTAINMENT MERCHANTS ASSN. BREYER, J., dissenting Appendix A to the opinion of BREYER, J. tion Versus Observation, 15 J. Applied Developmental Psychology 125 (1994). Carnagey, Anderson, & Bartholow, Media Violence and Social Neuroscience: New Questions and New Opportu nities, 16 Current Directions in Psychological Science 178 (2007). Carnagey & Anderson, Violent Video Game Exposure and Aggression: A Literature Review, 45 Minerva Psichiat rica 1 (2004). Carnagey & Anderson, The Effects of Reward and Pun ishment in Violent Video Games on Aggressive Affect, Cognition, and Behavior, 16 Psychological Science: J. Am. Psychological Society 882 (2005). Carnagey, Anderson, & Bushman, The Effect of Video Game Violence on Physiological Desensitization to Real life Violence, 43 J. Experimental Soc. Psychology 489 (2007). Chambers & Ascione, The Effects of Prosocial and Aggres sive Videogames on Childrenâs Donating and Helping, 148 J. Genetic Psychology: Research and Theory on Hu man Development 499 (1987). Chory & Cicchirillo, The Relationship Between Video Game Play and Trait Verbal Aggressiveness: An Appli cation of the General Aggression Model, 24 Communica tions Research Reports 113 (2007). Cicchirillo & Chory-Assad, Effects of Affective Orientation and Video Game Play on Aggressive Thoughts and Be haviors, 49 J. Broadcasting & Electronic Media 435 (2005). Colwell & Payne, Negative Correlates of Computer Game Play in Adolescents, 91 British J. Psychology 295 (2000). Cooper & Mackie, Video Games and Aggression in Chil dren, 16 J. Applied Soc. Psychology 726 (1986). Deselms & Altman, Immediate and Prolonged Effects of Videogame Violence, 33 J. Applied Soc. Psychology 1553 (2003). Cite as: 564 U. S. ____ (2011) 25 BREYER, J., dissenting Appendix A to the opinion of BREYER, J. Dill & Dill, Video Game Violence: A Review of the Empiri cal Literature, 3 Aggression & Violent Behavior 407 (1998). DoÄan, Video Games and Children: Violence in Video Games, 44 Yeni Symposium 161 (2006). Eastin, Video Game Violence and the Female Game Player: Self- and Opponent Gender Effects on Presence and Aggressive Thoughts, 32 Human Communication Research 351 (2006). Emes, Is Mr Pac Man Eating Our Children? A Review of the Effect of Video Games on Children, 42 Canadian J. Psychiatry 409 (1997). Farrar, Krcmar, & Nowak, Contextual Features of Violent Video Games, Mental Models, and Aggression, 56 J. Communication 387 (2006). Fischer, KastenmĂŒller, & Greitemeyer, Media Violence and the Self: The Impact of Personalized Gaming Char acters in Aggressive Video Games on Aggressive Behav ior, 46 J. Experimental Soc. Psychology 192 (2010). Funk, Childrenâs Exposure to Violent Video Games and Desensitization to Violence, 14 Child & Adolescent Psy chiatric Clinics North Am. 387 (2005). Funk, Video Games, 16 Adolescent Med. Clinics 395 (2005). Funk, Baldacci, Pasold, & Baumgardner, Violence Expo sure in Real-Life, Video Games, Television, Movies, and the Internet: Is There Desensitization? 27 J. Adolescence 23 (2004). Funk, Buchman, Jenks, & Bechtoldt, Playing Violent Video Games, Desensitization, and Moral Evaluation in Children, 24 J. Applied Developmental Psychology 413 (2003). Funk et al., Aggression and Psychopathology in Adoles cents with a Preference for Violent Electronic Games, 28 Aggressive Behavior 134 (2002). Funk, Buchman, Jenks, & Bechtoldt, An Evidence-Based 26 BROWN v. ENTERTAINMENT MERCHANTS ASSN. BREYER, J., dissenting Appendix A to the opinion of BREYER, J. Approach to Examining the Impact of Playing Violent Video and Computer Games, SIMILE: Studies in Media & Information Literacy Educ., vol. 2, no. 4, p. 1 (Nov. 2002). Gentile & Stone, Violent Video Game Effects on Children and Adolescents: A Review of the Literature, 57 Minerva Pediatrica 337 (2005). Gentile et al., The Effects of Prosocial Video Games on Prosocial Behaviors: International Evidence From Corre lational, Longitudinal, and Experimental Studies, 35 Personality & Soc. Psychology Bull. 752 (2009). Gentile, Lynch, Linder, & Walsh, The Effects of Violent Video Game Habits on Adolescent Hostility, Aggressive Behaviors, and School Performance, 27 J. Adolescence 5 (2004). Gentile & Gentile, Violent Video Games as Exemplary Teachers: A Conceptual Analysis, 37 J. Youth & Adoles cence 127 (2008). Giumetti & Markey, Violent Video Games and Anger as Predictors of Aggression, 41 J. Research in Personality 1234 (2007). Graybill, Kirsch, & Esselman, Effects of Playing Violent Versus Nonviolent Video Games on the Aggressive Idea tion of Aggressive and Nonaggressive Children, 15 Child Study J. 199 (1985). Grigoryan, Stepanyan, Stepanyan, & Agababyan, Influ ence of Aggressive Computer Games on the Brain Cortex Activity Level in Adolescents, 33 Human Physiology 34 (2007). Hastings et al., Young Childrenâs Video/Computer Game Use: Relations With School Performance and Behavior, 30 Issues in Mental Health Nursing 638 (2009). Huesmann, Nailing the Coffin Shut on Doubts That Vio lent Video Games Stimulate Aggression: Comment on Anderson et al., 136 Psychological Bull. 179 (2010). Huesmann, The Impact of Electronic Media Violence: Cite as: 564 U. S. ____ (2011) 27 BREYER, J., dissenting Appendix A to the opinion of BREYER, J. Scientific Theory and Research, 41 J. Adolescent Health S6 (2007). Huesmann & Taylor, The Role of Media Violence in Vio lent Behavior, 27 Annual Rev. Public Health 393 (2006). Hummer et al., Short-Term Violent Video Game Play by Adolescents Alters Prefrontal Activity During Cognitive Inhibition, 13 Media Psychology 136 (2010). Irwin & Gross, Cognitive Temp, Violent Video Games, and Aggressive Behavior in Young Boys, 10 J. Family Vio lence 337 (1995). Kirsh & Mounts, Violent Video Game Play impacts Facial Emotion Recognition, 33 Aggressive Behavior 353 (2007). Kirsh, Mounts, & Olczak, Violent Media Consumption and the Recognition of Dynamic Facial Expressions, 21 J. Interpersonal Violence 571 (2006). Kirsh, Olczak, & Mounts, Violent Video Games Induce an Affect Processing Bias, 7 Media Psychology 239 (2005). Kirsh, The Effects of Violent Video Games on Adolescents: The Overlooked Influence of Development, 8 Aggression & Violent Behavior 377 (2003). Kirsh, Seeing the World Through Mortal Kombat-Colored Glasses: Violent Video Games and the Development of a Short-term Hostile Attribution Bias, 5 Childhood 177 (1998). Konijn, Bijvank, & Bushman, I Wish I Were a Warrior: The Role of Wishful Identification in the Effects of Vio lent Video Games on Aggression in Adolescent Boys, 43 Developmental Psychology 1038 (2007). KrahĂ© & Möller, Playing Violent Electronic Games, Hos tile Attributional Style, and Aggression-related Norms in German Adolescents, 27 J. Adolescence 53 (2004). Krcmar, Farrar, & McGloin, The Effects of Video Game Realism on Attention, Retention and Aggressive Out comes, 27 Computers in Human Behavior 432 (2011). Krcmar & Lachlan, Aggressive Outcomes and Videogame 28 BROWN v. ENTERTAINMENT MERCHANTS ASSN. BREYER, J., dissenting Appendix A to the opinion of BREYER, J. Play: The Role of Length of Play and the Mechanisms at Work, 12 Media Psychology 249 (2009). Krcmar & Farrar, Retaliatory Aggression and the Effects of Point of View and Blood in Violent Video Games, 12 Mass Communication & Society 115 (2009). Kronenberger et al., Media Violence Exposure in Aggres sive and Control Adolescents: Differences in Self- and Parent-Reported Exposure to Violence on Television and in Video Games, 31 Aggressive Behavior 201 (2005). Kronenberger et al., Media Violence Exposure and Execu tive Functioning in Aggressive and Control Adolescents, 61 J. Clinical Psychology 725 (2005). Kuntsche, Hostility Among Adolescents in Switzerland? Multivariate Relations Between Excessive Media Use and Forms of Violence, 34 J. Adolescent Health 230 (2004). Lee, Peng, & Klein, Will the Experience of Playing a Vio lent Role in a Video Game Influence Peopleâs Judgments of Violent Crimes? 26 Computers in Human Behavior 1019 (2010). Lemmens & Bushman, The Appeal of Violent Video Games to Lower Educated Aggressive Adolescent Boys From Two Countries, 9 CyberPsychology & Behavior 638 (2006). Mathiak & Weber, Toward Brain Correlates of Natural Behavior: fMRI During VIolent Video Games, 27 Human Brain Mapping 948 (2006). Möller & KrahĂ©, Exposure to Violent Video Games and Aggression in German Adolescents: A Longitudinal Analysis, 35 Aggressive Behavior 75 (2009). Nowak, Krcmar, & Farrar, The Causes and Consequences of Presence: Considering the Influence of Violent Video Games on Presence and Aggression, 17 Presence: Teleop erators & Virtual Environments 256 (2008). Olson et al., M-Rated Video Games and Aggressive or Problem Behavior Among Young Adolescents, 13 Applied Cite as: 564 U. S. ____ (2011) 29 BREYER, J., dissenting Appendix A to the opinion of BREYER, J. Developmental Science 188 (2009). Panee & Ballard, High Versus Low Aggressive Priming During Video-Game Training: Effects on Violent Action During Game Play, Hostility, Heart Rate, and Blood Pressure, 32 J. Applied Soc. Psychology 2458 (2002). Persky & Blascovich, Immersive Virtual Environments Versus Traditional Platforms: Effects of Violent and Nonviolent Video Game Play, 10 Media Psychology 135 (2007). Persky & Blascovich, Immersive Virtual Video Game Play and Presence: Influences on Aggressive Feelings and Behavior, 17 Presence: Teleoperators & Virtual Envi ronments 57 (2008). Polman, de Castro, & van Aken, Experimental Study of the Differential Effects of Playing Versus Watching Vio lent Video Games on Childrenâs Aggressive Behavior, 34 Aggressive Behavior 256 (2008). Potera, Sex and Violence in the Media Influence Teen Behavior: Three Studies Show a Correlation, 109 Ameri can J. Nursing 20 (2009). Richmond & Wilson, Are Graphic Media Violence, Aggres sion, and Moral Disengagement Related? 15 Psychiatry, Psychology & Law 350 (2008). Schaefer & Harrison, The Effects of Violent Fantasy on Childrenâs Aggressive Behavior, 41 Psychology & Educ. 35 (2004). Schmierbach, âKilling Spreeâ: Exploring the Connection Between Competitive Game Play and Aggressive Cogni tion, 37 Communication Research 256 (2010). Sheese & Graziano, Deciding to Defect: The Effects of Video-Game Violence on Cooperative Behavior, 16 Psy chological Science: J. Am. Psychological Society 354 (2005). Sherry, The Effects of Violent Video Games on Aggression. A Meta-Analysis, 27 Human Communication Research 409 (2001). 30 BROWN v. ENTERTAINMENT MERCHANTS ASSN. BREYER, J., dissenting Appendix A to the opinion of BREYER, J. Shibuya, Sakamoto, Ihori, & Yukawa, The Effects of the Presence and Contexts of Video Game Violence on Chil dren: A Longitudinal Study in Japan, 39 Simulation & Gaming 528 (2008). Sigurdsson, Gudjonsson, Bragason, Kristjansdottir, & Sigfusdottir, The Role of Violent Cognition in the Rela tionship Between Personality and the Involvement in Violent Films and Computer Games, 41 Personality & Individual Differences 381 (2006). Silvern & Williamson, The Effects of Video Game Play on Young Childrenâs Aggression, Fantasy, and Prosocial behavior, 8 J. Applied Developmental Psychology 453 (1987). Slater, Henry, Swaim, & Cardador, Vulnerable Teens, Vulnerable Times: How Sensation Seeking, Alienation, and Victimization Moderate the Violent Media Con tentâAggressiveness Relation, 31 Communication Re search 642 (2004). Slater, Henry, Swaim, & Anderson, Violent Media Content and Aggressiveness in Adolescents: A Downward Spiral Model, 30 Communication Research 713 (2003). Staude-MĂŒller, Bliesener, & Luthman, Hostile and Hard ened? An Experimental Study on (De-)sensitization to Violence and Suffering Through Playing Video Games, 67 Swiss J. Psychology 41 (2008). Steward & Follina, Informing Policies in Forensic Set tings: A Review of Research Investigating the Effects of Exposure to Media Violence on Challenging/Offending Behaviour, 8 British J. Forensic Prac. 31 (2006). Swing & Anderson, The Unintended Negative Conse quences of Exposure to Violent Video games, 12 Int. J. Cognitive Tech. 3 (2007). Tamborini et al., Violent Virtual Video Games and Hostile Thoughts, 48 J. Broadcasting & Electronic Media 335 (2004). Uhlmann & Swanson, Exposure to Violent Video Games Cite as: 564 U. S. ____ (2011) 31 BREYER, J., dissenting Appendix A to the opinion of BREYER, J. Increases Automatic Aggressiveness, 27 J. Adolescence 41 (2004). Vaughan, Inadvertent Script Change and Increased Pro pensity for Violence: The Danger of Interactive Video Games, 34 Transactional Analysis J. 30 (2004). Wallenius & PunamĂ€ki, Digital Game Violence and Direct Aggression in Adolescence: A Longitudinal Study of the Roles of Sex, Age, and Parent-Child Communication, 29 J. Applied Developmental Psychology 286 (2008). Wallenius, PunamĂ€ki, & RimpelĂ€, Digital Game Playing and Direct and Indirect Aggression in Early Adoles cence: The Roles of Age, Social Intelligence, and Parent- Child Communication, 36 J. Youth and Adolescence 325 (2007). Wang et al., Short Term Exposure to a Violent Video Game Induces Changes in Frontolimbic Circuitry in Adolescents, 3 Brain Imaging & Behavior 38 (2009). Weber, Ritterfeld, & Mathiak, Does Playing Violent Video Games Induce Aggression? Empirical Evidence of a Functional Magnetic Resonance Imaging Study, 8 Media Psychology 39 (2006). Wiegman & van Schie, Video Game Playing and its Rela tions With Aggressive and Prosocial Behaviour, 37 Brit ish J. Soc. Psychology 367 (1998). Williams, The Effects of Frustration, Violence, and Trait Hostility After Playing a Video Game, 12 Mass Commu nication & Society 291 (2009). Ybarra et al., Linkages Between Internet and Other Me dia Violence With Seriously Violent Behavior by Youth, 122 Pediatrics 929 (2008). 32 BROWN v. ENTERTAINMENT MERCHANTS ASSN. BREYER, J., dissenting Appendix B to the opinion of BREYER, J. B Bensley & Van Eenwyk, Video Games and Real-Life Ag gression: Review of the Literature, 29 J. Adolescent Health 244 (2001). Bösche, Violent Content Enhances Video Game Perform ance, 21 J. Media Psychology: Theories, Methods, and Applications 145 (2009). Colwell & Kato, Video Game Play in British and Japanese Adolescents, 36 Simulation & Gaming 518 (2005). Colwell & Kato, Investigation of the Relationship Between Social Isolation, Self-Esteem, Aggression and Computer Game Play in Japanese Adolescents, 6 Asian J. Soc. Psy chology 149 (2003). Dominick, Videogames, Television Violence, and Aggres sion in Teenagers, 34 J. Communication 136 (1984). Ferguson, Blazing Angels or Resident Evil? Can Violent Video Games be a Force For Good? 14 Rev. Gen. Psy chology 68 (2010). Ferguson, Violent Video Games: Dogma, Fear, Pseudo science, 33 Skeptical Inquirer 38 (2009). Ferguson, The Good, The Bad and the Ugly: A Meta analytic Review of Positive and Negative Effects of Vio lent Video Games, 78 Psychiatric Q. 309 (2007). Ferguson & Meehan, Saturday Nightâs Alright for Fight ing: Antisocial Traits, Fighting, and Weapons Carrying in a Large Sample of Youth, 81 Psychiatric Q. 293 (2010). Ferguson et al., Violent Video Games and Aggression, 35 Crim. Justice & Behavior 311 (2008). Ferguson, Research on the Effects of Violent Video Games: A Critical Analysis, 3 Soc. & Personality Psychology Compass 351 (2009). Ferguson & Rueda, The Hitman Study: Violent Video Game Exposure Effects on Aggressive Behavior, Hostile Feelings, and Depression, 15 European Psychologist 99 (2010). Cite as: 564 U. S. ____ (2011) 33 BREYER, J., dissenting Appendix B to the opinion of BREYER, J. Ferguson, San Miguel, & Hartley, A Multivariate Analysis of Youth Violence and Aggression: The Influence of Fam ily, Peers, Depression, and Media Violence, 155 J. Pedi atrics 904 (2009). Ferguson, Evidence for Publication Bias in Video Game Violence Effects Literature: A Meta-Analytic Review, 12 Aggression & Violent Behavior 470 (2007). Ferguson, The School Shooting/Violent Video Game Link: Causal Relationship or Moral Panic? 5 J. Investigative Psychology & Offender Profiling 25 (2008). Ferguson et al., Personality, Parental, and Media Influ ences on Aggressive Personality and Violent Crime in Young Adults, 17 J. Aggression, Maltreatment & Trauma 395 (2008). Ferguson & Kilburn, Much Ado About Nothing: The Mis estimation and Overinterpretation of Violent Video Game Effects in Eastern and Western Nations: Com ment on Anderson et al. (2010), 136 Psychological Bull. 174 (2010). Fleming & Rickwood, Effects of Violent Versus Nonviolent Video Games on Children's Arousal, Aggressive Mood, and Positive Mood, 31 J. Applied Soc. Psychology 2047 (2001). Griffiths, Violent Video Games and Aggression: A Review of the Literature, 4 Aggression & Violent Behavior 203 (1999). Griffiths, Video Games and Aggression, 10 The Psycholo gist 397 (1997). Ivory & Kalyanaraman, The Effects of Technological Advancement and Violent Content in Video Games on Players' Feelings of Presence, Involvement, Physiological Arousal, and Aggression, 57 J. Communication 532 (2007). Kestenbaum & Weinstein, Personality, Psychopathology, and Developmental Issues in Male Adolescent Video Game Use, 24 J. Am. Academy Child Psychology 329 (1985). 34 BROWN v. ENTERTAINMENT MERCHANTS ASSN. BREYER, J., dissenting Appendix B to the opinion of BREYER, J. Markey & Markey, Vulnerability to Violent Video Games: A Review and Integration of Personality Research, 14 Rev. Gen. Psychology 82 (2010). Markey & Scherer, An Examination of Psychoticism and Motion Capture Controls as Moderators of the Effects of Violent Video Games, 25 Computers in Human Behavior 407 (2009). Mitrofan, Paul, & Spencer, Is Aggression in Children With Behavioural and Emotional Difficulties Associated With Television Viewing and Video Game Playing? A System atic Review, 35 Child: Care, Health & Development 5 (2009). Olson, Media Violence Research and Youth Violence Data: Why Do They Conflict? 28 Academic Psychiatry 144 (2004). Porter & Starcevic, Are Violent Video Games Harmful? 15 Australasian Psychiatry 422 (2007). Regenbogen, Herrmann, & Fehr, The Neural Processing of Voluntary Completed, Real and Virtual Violent and NonViolent Computer Game Scenarios Displaying Pre defined Actions in Gamers and Nongamers, 5 Soc. Neu roscience 221 (2010). Scott, The Effect of Video Games on Feelings of Aggres sion, 129 J. Psychology 121 (1995). Sestir & Bartholow, Violent and Nonviolent Video Games Produce Opposing Effects on Aggressive and Prosocial Outcomes, 46 J. Experimental Soc. Psychology 934 (2010). Unsworth, Devilly, & Ward, The Effect of Playing Violent Video Games on Adolescents: Should Parents be Quak ing in Their Boots? 13 Psychology, Crime & Law 383 (2007). Unsworth & Ward, Video Games and Aggressive Behavior. 36 Australian Psychologist 184 (2001). Williams & Skoric, Internet Fantasy Violence: A Test of Aggression in an Online Game, 72 Communication Cite as: 564 U. S. ____ (2011) 35 BREYER, J., dissenting Appendix B to the opinion of BREYER, J. Monographs 217 (2005). Winkel, Novak, & Hopson, Personality Factors, Subject Gender, and the Effects of Aggressive Video Games on Aggression in Adolescents, 21 J. Research in Personality 211 (1987).